Interpretation and Method Empirical Research Methods and the Interpretive Turn

(Ann) #1

280 ANALYZING DATA


his own categories and conceptual tools. To the extent that ethnographic analysis tries to simultaneously
highlight both hermeneutic circles under discussion here, it moves closer to the model that I sketch later in
the chapter.


  1. “Structural” prosthetics—those that conceptualize events as occupying relatively determinate posi-
    tions relative to other events and institutions and that seek to delineate a kind of transcendental grammar
    governing those relations—replicate the problems of the single hermeneutic analyses that emphasize the
    scholar’s active interpretive role. “Agentic” prosthetics either operate with a more or less determinate con-
    ception of the interests and preferences of social actors, in a neopositivist manner, or replicate the second set
    of problems by trying merely to describe what those actors think and do. Both kinds of prosthetic are
    certainly available for scholarly use, but neither fulfills the imperative of preserving agency as well as the
    “processual/relational” (P.T. Jackson and Nexon 1999) prosthetic on offer here.

  2. “Legitimation” is not the only process that can be conceptualized in this manner, of course;
    “routinization” and “institutionalization” have been similarly reconfigured by other scholars.

  3. Technically, what I am proposing here is a relational social constructionism: relational inasmuch as
    it analytically privileges “bonds” rather than “essences” and dynamic social ties rather than static social and
    constitutive relations (Tilly 1998, 18–22); constructionist inasmuch as it emphasizes contingency rather
    than naturalistic inevitability (Hacking 1999, 6–7); and social inasmuch as it focuses on action (behavior
    plus meaning) rather than behavior conceptually devoid of meaning (Parsons 1954a, 234–35; M. Weber
    1976, 11–12; Ringmar 1996, 66). The extent to which this is a form of “interpretivism” broadly understood
    remains, to my mind, an open question, particularly since many forms of interpretivist analysis eschew or at
    least minimize causation and causality (Geertz 1973a, 5).

  4. Serious practitioners of these techniques make no such claims. But at the same time they are not as
    clear as they might be about the ideal-typical character of their analyses.

  5. Genealogical analysis enjoys a broad and varied history. The procedure was initially pioneered by
    Friedrich Nietzsche at the end of the nineteenth century (Nietzsche 1967) as a critique of the Enlightenment
    philosophical project of integrating diverse social phenomena under the banner of Reason centered on the
    knowing subject. Genealogical analysis involves, among other things, a suspension of the temptation toward
    functionalism and teleological reasoning characteristic of much of classical social thought, and a focus
    instead on how the exercise of power affects the subsequent meaning that we assign to some piece of social
    life. Michel Foucault refined the procedure in his seminal studies of prisons and sexuality (Foucault 1978,



  1. and is perhaps the single most important figure in the development of this analytical technique.



  1. In a sense, “Western Civilization” is the mirror image of what Edward Said calls “orientalism” (Said
    1978). Where Said focuses on the “sense” that Europeans made of others, I focus more on the “sense” that
    Europeans (and some Americans) made of themselves.

  2. Before it was used in postwar German reconstruction debates, the commonplace was central to the
    case for militarism made during World War I, as well as an important component of the interwar effort to
    make sense of Germany’s defeat as indicative of a general civilizational crisis (P.T. Jackson 2006, chapter 4).

  3. Somewhat unreflectively, Samuel Huntington (1996) replicates this argument. I would suggest that
    the reason why aspects of his book have at least an intuitive plausibility is precisely the fact that it deploys an
    existing commonplace—“Western Civilization”—and taps one of its historical potentials.

  4. Although Fritz Ringer (1997, 111–6) provides an excellent discussion of Weber’s strategy of “singu-
    lar causal analysis,” his presentation does downplay the extent to which Weber’s delineation of causal mo-
    ments is ideal-typical rather than “objective” in a neopositivist sense (Ringer 1997, 70–71) and also
    misunderstands what Weber’s treatment does to the traditional notion of “objectivity” (Ringer 1997, 125–
    26; cf. Hennis 1988).

  5. As with the delineation of rhetorical commonplaces, this specification of causal mechanisms derives
    from my previous work on the subject. Other specifications are of course possible.

  6. “Abendland” is not simply the German word for “West.” There are at least two other terms—“West”
    and “Okzident”—that would also serve, so it is significant that Adenauer uses this term and not one of the
    available synonyms.

Free download pdf