Constructive Pneumatological Hermeneutics in Pentecostal Christianity

(Barry) #1
even exists apart from the conventionalist aspect of saying (as a matter of

linguistic convenience) that a text “means” something. 11

Thus authorial intention, linguistic sign, and readerly understanding

can all be defi ned as “meaning,” but only authorial intention and readerly

understanding can be said to have something real backing them—the real-

ity, that is, of cognitive events. 12 The notion of a non-intentionalist mean-

ing residing within the wording of a text has nothing real backing it—that

is, there is nothing within its conceptual frame that extends to or from a

real philosophical given. It owes its birth as a concept to the habit of refer-

ring to the intentions encoded within a text as the text’s own meaning.

Such a habit was once safe, of course, because in the days of yore hardly

anyone ever considered that meaning might be anything other than the

author’s intention. 13

It is important that I make my point clearly. The fact that common

parlance refers to “meaning” as if it were a native property of texts does

not validate that view. For the sake of comparison, we might consider how

normal linguistic usage departs from the better judgments of philosophy

in its handling of, say, the concepts of “love” and “hatred”—concepts

regularly handled as if they were things that really exist out there, inde-

pendently of lovers and haters. Everyday language treats love and hatred as

interpersonal contagions, and love is spoken of as something “in the air.”

If one had to arrive at a defi nition of “love” strictly on the basis of every-

day language, one would have little cause to think it was not some sort of

fl oating impersonal force. But it is rather evident, as I see it, that love is

not a transportable substance or an impersonal force, and there is no such

thing as love apart from the affections of lovers. The same goes for the

understanding of “meaning” implied by the existence of texts, and by the

call to read and understand those texts: there is no such thing as meaning

apart from the intentions of “meaners.”

It was only when a rather untidy line of thinking mistook a habit of

parlance for a description of how authors relate to texts that the concept

of meaning came to be cut loose from the intentionalist aspect of writing.

This de-intentionalized concept of meaning eventually found enough of

a reception to become a fi xture of hermeneutic discussion, thanks partly

to its receiving a permanent home within the phenomenalists’ reinven-

tion of the world as something explicable without reference to originary

moments. This seems to be the source of the idea of viewing meaning

as an impersonal force—as a fl uid substance that transcends the events

of writing and reading. It would be diffi cult to overestimate the effect

70 J.C. POIRIER

Free download pdf