Philosophy Now-Aug-Sept 2019

(Joyce) #1
20 Philosophy Now ●August/September 2019 Interview

recently involved in organising a very
exciting joint meeting of the Royal Soci-
ety and the British Academy, the leading
UK academies for the natural sciences
and the social sciences and humanities
respectively, on the state of evolutionary
theory in the light of recent research in
areas such as niche construction, epige-
netics, and symbiosis. Among other
things, this drew attention, I hope, to the
value of bringing together narrow and
deep expertise in the sciences with
wider, more synoptic perspectives from
the humanities. Or in a critical vein, I
have argued that evolutionary psycholo-
gists have failed to keep up with devel-
opments in evolutionary theory that
make much of what they say highly
problematic.

I like to think that there’s no sharp border-
line between a theoretical scientific discipline
and the philosophy of that discipline; for
instance philosophy of physics and theoretical
physics. Many ‘paradigm-shifting’ scientific
discoveries involve changing some very basic
ways we see important aspects of the world,
so perhaps these discoveries should be consid-
ered ‘metaphysical’ as well as ‘scientific’.
What is your stance on this?
I certainly agree that the two aspects – if
there are two! – are closely interconnect-
ed; but I’m inclined to think that there
are important divisions of labour and
expertise. Scientists and philosophers
have very different training and usually
very different intellectual experience. I’d
say that that was much of the reason why
it’s so valuable for them to talk to one
another. But certainly I would agree that
major theoretical shifts are often as
much philosophical as empirical.

Would you be prepared to call yourself a the-
oretical biologist?
Well, I’d prefer to have biologists decide
whether to call me one. They have occa-
sionally, and I’m generally quite happy
when they do so. I would say, though,
that most of my work is definitely meant
to be philosophy; and as I mentioned,
although scientists and philosophers are
often interested in the same questions,
there are important differences in the
approaches and skills they are likely to
bring to those questions.

Hello Professor. There have been many dis-
cussions about what the contribution of phi-
losophy of science is to science itself. Some
famous scientists have even claimed that
philosophy has made no contribution to sci-
ence. I am interested in your strategy and
arguments on this matter.
I suppose that the most famous attacks
on philosophy have come from physi-
cists, and I’ll leave the philosophers of
physics to respond to those. As the
philosopher Thomas Kuhn taught us –
rightly, I think – a great many scientists
do relatively routine work in a well-
established paradigm, and have no
strong interest in foundational issues in
general, or philosophy in particular.
Biologists too, I think, are mostly indif-
ferent to philosophy. But a small yet
influential minority have thought that
philosophy of biology was important for
their science. Notable among these, and
very important to the growth of the
field, have been the formidable figures
of Ernst Mayr and Richard Lewontin.
Many of the leading philosophers of
biology in the 70s and 80s (though not
myself) spent time in Lewontin’s labora-
tory. Other prominent biologists who
have been interested in philosophical
issues and in interacting with philoso-
phers include Denis Noble, Scott
Gilbert and Ford Doolittle.
At this stage in my career I find the
importance of biology for philosophy
very obvious. Life generally, and human
life in particular, are surely central top-
ics of philosophical interest that can also
only benefit from attention to the scien-
tific knowledge that has been gained
about them. What philosophers can
contribute to biology is perhaps not so
obvious; perhaps most biologists can do
their work very well without addressing
many philosophical questions.
One answer that resonates with my
own experience is that whereas scientists
are professionally required to look
deeply into very specific questions,
philosophers have the privilege of rang-
ing over a much wider, if shallower, ter-
rain. This sometimes enables them to
see points where distinct scientific pro-
jects need to be brought into closer con-
tact with one another. I see a good deal
of my own work in this way. I was

John


Dupré


isProfessor of


Philosophy of Science at


the University of Exeter


and Director of Egenis,


the Centre for the Study


of Life Sciences. He was


recently elected


President of the


Philosophy of Science


Association.


Edit Talpsepp-Randla


talks to him about the


philosophy of biology.


PO


RT
RA
IT
©^
GU


IDO


CA


STA


GN


OL
I


Science

Free download pdf