126 ROBERT D. VAN VALIN, JR.
(114) a. try' (John, [[do' (John)] CAUSE [BECOME clean' (clock)]])
b. [say' (Mary, John)] CAUSE [BECOME want' (John, [[do'
(John)] CAUSE [BECOME clean' (clock)]])
[say' (Mary, John)] CAUSE [BECOME obligated' (Mary,
[[do' (Mary)] CAUSE [BECOME clean' (clock)]])
The revised linking procedure for English, based on (86), is given in (115),
and the Completeness Constraint [CC] is repeated in (116).
(115) Linking from Logical Structure to Syntactic Structure
- Determine the semantic roles of the arguments, based on
their position in the decomposed semantic structure. - Determine actor and undergoer assignments, following the
Α-U Hierarchy in (25). - Assign pragmatic functions (topic, focus) to the elements in
the clause. - Assign actor and undergoer to specific morphosyntactic func
tions.
a. This is language-specific (see 39).
b. In syntactically accusative languages, the accessibility to
pivot is A > U. - Assign the remaining core arguments their appropriate case
markers/prepositions. - If there is a focus NP which is [+WH], then assign it to the
PCS.
(116) Completeness Constraint: all of the arguments explicitly
specified in the logical structure of a verb must be realized syn
tactically in any clause containing that verb, and all of the argu
ments in the syntax must be linked to an argument position in a
LS.
The only additional statements required for the linking are first, the specifi
cation that two arguments from distinct LS may be linked to the same mor
phosyntactic function if and only if they are identical, and second, the
theory of control. This theory was proposed in FVV, section 6.5, and has
been elaborated in Cutrer (1987, this volume). It is summarized in (117).
(117) Theory of obligatory control
a. Causative and directive speech act verbs have undergoer
control.
b. All other verbs have actor control.