Dictionary of Philosophy of Religion

(Amelia) #1
xxi

Introduction

There are many points at which continental philosophy can be seen as comple-
menting classical and mainstream philosophy of religion, but some elements of conti-
nental thought are pitted against traditional philosophy of religion which is sometimes
called “onto-theology.” The latter privileges the theoretical clarity, explanations of the
cosmos, divine attributes, rules of evidence, and so on. Merold Westphal is a repre-
sentative of those working in the continental tradition who believes that philosophy of
religion should be so structured that it privileges the practical life of faith. We s t p h a l
develops his position as a Christian inspired by Martin Heidegger:

the goal of theology “is never a valid system of theological prepositions” but rather
“concrete Christian experience itself.”... [B]ecause its goal is the praxis of the believer as
a distinctive mode of existence, “theology in its essence is a practical science.” Unlike onto-
theology, theology properly understood is “innately homiletical”... It is as if Heidegger is
saying, I have found it necessary to deny theory in order to make room for practice.^1

Westphal further articulates his position in connection with a novel by C. S. Lewis (Till
We Have Faces) in which a main character loses her beloved (the god, psyche) because
she seeks knowledge about the beloved.

The challenge of faith is the same: the believer is called upon to sustain a beautiful and
loving relationship through trust in a lover about whom she remains significantly (though
not totally) in the dark and who, though he gives himself to her freely, is not at her disposal.
The relationship is destroyed when the beloved... insists on Enlightenment, on the dissi-
pating the darkness of mystery with the light of human knowledge, on walking by sight
and not by faith.
To be able to resist this temptation, faith must deny theory, or, to be more precise, the
primacy of insight. For such faith, Plato’s divided line and Hegel’s modern vision thereof as the
movement “beyond faith” to knowledge are not the ascent from that which is inferior... to
that which is superior... ; they are rather the withdrawal from the site at which alone is
possible a loving, trusting relation with a God before whom one might sing and dance...
This love, this trust, this relationship—these are the practice for the sake of which it was
necessary to deny theory. This is not to abolish theology. It is to see that theology’s task is
to serve this life of faith, not the ideals of knowledge as defined by the philosophical
traditions.^2

This position calls for several observations. First, philosophy of religion has
demonstrated that, as a field, it is wide enough to include diverse projects, including
Westphal’s. Second, Westphal advances his preferred model of theology and philoso-
phy as a Christian. In a field with a plurality of religions represented, philosophers
will find it difficult to abandon questions of knowledge, inquiry about the truth or

CTaliaferro_FM_Final.indd xxi 6/17/2010 9:32:52 AM

Free download pdf