The Spartan Regime_ Its Character, Origins, and Grand Strategy - Paul Anthony Rahe

(Dana P.) #1

126 Appendix 1


helots to work it, and a guaranteed income.^5 With this general claim, Isocra-


tes (11.18) appears to be in agreement, and the same can be said for Polybius


(6.45, 48.3)—who, in passages in which he is clearly drawing on the diligent


and well-informed fourth-century historian Ephorus, asserts that no Spartan


was allowed to own more in the way of landed property than any other and


that every Spartan was guaranteed a share in what he calls the polıtıkē` chō ́ra.


It does not make sense to suppose that Plutarch blindly copied one ac-


count of the land-tenure system from one source and another from another


source. He was not a mere copyist slavishly following one earlier writer, then


another. When he wrote on a subject, he ordinarily read a great variety of


sources; he compared them with a critical eye, considering their relative plau-


sibility; and he either chose among them on grounds he specified or left it to


the reader to do the choosing.^6 In this case, it seems likely that his selection of


language in the first of these passages was misleading—that, in this passage,


what Plutarch meant to convey was that the elders of the tribe authorized the


assignment of an allotment to the boy and that in the other passages he de-


scribed the manner in which this system ordinarily operated: the transfer of


the klēˆros from the father to his son. When the citizen in possession of a klēˆros


had no son, possession could presumably be reassigned to the second or third


son of a citizen who was blessed with an abundance of male offspring. Accord-


ing to Plutarch (Mor. 238e), only those who completed the agōgē ́ could make


good on this claim, and anyone of citizen birth who successfully did so had


the right to an allotment.^7


Such an arrangement was proposed by the Athenian Stranger in Plato’s


Laws (5.745b–e, 11.923c–924a); and, like other institutions suggested by Pla-


to’s chief interlocutor, it may well be a variation on a Spartan original. One


might, of course, argue that the Stranger’s failure to make explicit reference to


Lacedaemon in the pertinent passages proves that no such arrangement ever


existed at Sparta,^8 and it is true that the Athenian Stranger sometimes ac-


knowledges to his Spartan and Cretan companions the source of his inspira-


tion. But he does not always do so, especially when his debt would have been


obvious to well-informed contemporaries;^9 and we must remember that The


Laws is a dialogue, not a treatise, and that its author was not a pedant eager to


establish his bona fides by footnoting his sources, but a great artist intent on


achieving in his description of the conversation a measure of dramatic verisi-


militude. Plutarch (Agis 5) tells us that, in the aftermath of the Peloponnesian


War, a Spartan ephor named Epitadeus quarreled with his son and, in order to

Free download pdf