The Philosophy Book

(nextflipdebug2) #1

59


Plato and Aristotle differed in their
opinion of the nature of universal
qualities. For Plato, they reside in the
higher realm of the Forms, but for
Aristotle they reside here on Earth.

now call the biological sciences,
whereas Plato’s background had
been firmly based in mathematics.
This difference in background
helps to explain the difference in
approach between the two men.
Mathematics, especially geometry,
deals with abstract concepts that
are far removed from the everyday
world, whereas biology is very much
about the world around us, and is
based almost solely on observation.
Plato sought confirmation of a realm
of Forms from notions such as the
perfect circle (which cannot exist
in nature), but Aristotle found that
certain constants can be discovered
by examining the natural world.


Trusting the senses
What Aristotle proposed turned
Plato’s theory on its head. Far from
mistrusting our senses, Aristotle
relied on them for the evidence


to back up his theories. What he
learnt from studying the natural
world was that by observing the
characteristics of every example
of a particular plant or animal that
he came across, he could build up
a complete picture of what it was
that distinguished it from other
plants or animals, and deduce what
makes it what it is. His own studies
confirmed what he already
believed—that we are not born
with an innate ability to recognize
Forms, as Plato maintained.
Each time a child comes across
a dog, for example, it notes what it
is about that animal that it has in
common with other dogs, so that
it can eventually recognize the
things that make something a
dog. The child now has an idea
of “dogginess”, or the “form”, as
Aristotle puts it, of a dog. In this
way, we learn from our experience

of the world what the shared
characteristics are that make
things what they are—and
the only way of experiencing
the world is through our senses.

The essential form of things
Like Plato, then, Aristotle is
concerned with finding some kind of
immutable and eternal bedrock in a
world characterized by change, but
he concludes that there is no need
to look for this anchor in a world of
Forms that are only perceptible to
the soul. The evidence is here in the
world around us, perceptible through
the senses. Aristotle believes that
things in the material world are not
imperfect copies of some ideal
Form of themselves, but that the
essential form of a thing is actually
inherent in each instance of that
thing. For example, “dogginess”
is not just a shared characteristic
of dogs—it is something that is
inherent in each and every dog. ❯❯

See also: Socrates 46–49 ■ Plato 50–55 ■ Avicenna 76–79 ■ Averroes 82–83 ■ René Descartes 116–123 ■
John Locke 130–33 ■ Gottfried Leibniz 134–37 ■ George Berkeley 138–41 ■ David Hume 148–53 ■ Immanuel Kant 164–71


THE ANCIENT WORLD


Everything that
depends on the action
of nature is by nature
as good as it can be.
Aristotle
Free download pdf