The Ancient Greek Economy. Markets, Households and City-States

(Rick Simeone) #1

INTRODUCTION 27


philosophical idea which was at odds with popular conceptions of wealth. The


next section confirms this. Aristotle says that there is another type of acquisi-


tion, chrematistike, which aims at wealth without limit, and concedes that most


people think that it is identical with oikonomike (1.3.10.1256b40–1257a3).^128


Aristotle finds this view mistaken because the latter is in accordance with


nature, but the former is not. Here it is clear that the distinction is that of


Aristotle, made on the basis of his philosophical notions of what is natural and


what is not. Further on in the same chapter he refers to those who believe that


it is the function of oikonomike either to maintain one’s financial assets (nomi-


smatos ousian) or to increase them to infinity (1.3.1257b38–41). Once again,


it is clear that Aristotle’s views about the acquisition of wealth should not be


taken as representative of Greek attitudes in general. If one reads the text of


the Politics carefully, one discovers that the science of oikonomia, managing a


household, was on the traditional view aimed at increasing one’s assets, which


implies production for sale in the market.


The popular attitudes to which Aristotle refers are more fully expressed in

Xenophon’s Oeconomicus, or The Estate-Manager. The aim of the dialogue is


to understand the nature of oikonomia, that is, the skill of managing the oikos,


one’s property.^129 When the dialogue opens, Critobulus is looking for someone


who can teach him to manage his property (Xen. Oec. 1.1–3). The person who


possesses this skill can ‘by taking over the estate of someone else pay all neces-


sary taxes and by making a surplus, increase his assets’ (Xen. Oec. 1.4). Socrates


has a moralistic view of what constitutes an asset; for him anything that does


damage to the moral character of its owner does not count as an asset (Xen.


Oec. 1.7–20). Assuming that the owner is morally good, however, his aim will


still be to increase their property (Xen. Oec. 2.1). This skill does not just enable


men to provide for their needs; it makes them capable of increasing their assets


if they work (Xen. Oec. 1.16). Critobulus asks for Socrates’ advice because ‘I see


that you understand one aspect of creating wealth: making a surplus. So I hope


that someone who makes a surplus out of little can very easily make a large


surplus out of much’ (Xen. Oec. 2.10). After some discussion Socrates says, ‘we


concluded that estate management (oikonomia) is the name of a certain type of


knowledge, and this knowledge was clearly that by which men increase their


property, and that their property was the total amount of what they acquire’


(Xen. Oec. 6.4). Ischomachus says that his father would buy uncultivated plots


of land, make improvements on them, then sell them for a profit (Xen. Oec.


20.26). Socrates compares his father to a merchant who buys grain, then sells it


wherever he can find the highest price. Despite the difference in social status,


the merchant and the gentleman farmer are united in their pursuit of profit.


Socrates therefore concludes that ‘all men love by nature those things that they


think will bring them benefits’ (Xen. Oec. 20.29).

Free download pdf