A Short History of the Middle Ages Fourth Edition

(Marvins-Underground-K-12) #1

new schools, while masters and students who studied the quadrivium generally did so


outside of the classroom.


Scholars looked to logic to clarify what they knew and lead them to further


knowledge. That God existed, nearly everyone believed. But a scholar like Anselm of


Bec (whom we met above, p. 174, as the archbishop of Canterbury) was not


satisfied by belief alone. Anselm’s faith, as he put it, “sought understanding.” He


emptied his mind of all concepts except that of God; then, using the tools of logic, he


proved God’s very existence in his Monologion. In Paris a bit later, Peter Abelard


declared that “nothing can be believed unless it is first understood.” He drew together


conflicting authoritative texts on 158 key subjects in his Sic et non (Yes and No),


including “That God is one and the contrary” and “That it is permitted to kill men


and the contrary.” Leaving the propositions unresolved, Abelard urged his students to


discover the reasons behind the disagreements and find ways to reconcile them. Soon


Peter Lombard (c.1100–1160) adopted Abelard’s method of juxtaposing opposing


positions, but he supplied his own reasoned resolutions as well. His Sententiae was


perhaps the most successful theology textbook of the entire Middle Ages.


One key logical issue for twelfth-century scholars involved the question of


“universals”: whether a universal—something that can be said of many—is real or


simply a linguistic or mental entity. Abelard argued that “things either individually or


collectively cannot be called universal, i.e., said to be predicated of many.” He was


maintaining a position later called “nominalist.”^10 The other view was the “realist”


position, which claimed that things “predicated of many” were universal and real. For


example, when we look at diverse individuals of one kind, say Luna and Sole, we say


of each of them that they are members of the same species: cat. Realists argued that


“cat” was real. Nominalists thought it a mere word.


Later in the twelfth century, scholars found precise tools in the works of Aristotle


to resolve this and other logical questions. During Abelard’s lifetime, very little of


Aristotle’s work was available in Europe because it had not been translated from


Greek into Latin. By the end of the century, however, that lack had been filled by


translators who traveled to Islamic or formerly Islamic cities—Toledo in Spain,


Palermo in Sicily—where Aristotle had already been translated into Arabic and


carefully commented on by Islamic scholars such as Ibn Sina (Avicenna; see p. 126


above) (980–1037) and Ibn Rushd (Averroes) (1126–1198). By the thirteenth


century, Aristotle had become the primary philosopher for the scholastics (the


scholars of medieval European universities).


The lofty subjects of the schools had down-to-earth, practical consequences in

Free download pdf