Free Will A Contemporary Introduction

(Marvins-Underground-K-12) #1

190 Seven Views of Contemporary Compatibilism


Nevertheless, he understood autonomy to be among the concepts in discussions
of moral responsibility (1995: 4). Mele understood autonomy as the capacity for
self- rule, and he looked to more basic features of self- control to explain the
phenomenon.
What does Mele have in mind by self- control? The opposite of weak will or
akrasia. He draws upon his account of weakness of will to help shed light on
weak will’s opposite, self­ control. According to Mele, weakness of will arises
when one’s motivational states become misaligned with one’s judgments about
the best (or better) course of action (1995: 7). Because evaluations of things one
desires can be out of line with the strength of one’s desires for those things,
one’s best judgments sometimes are in disharmony with one’s strongest desires
(desires that play a causal role in action) (25). It is in such cases of conflict that
the self- controlled as opposed to the weak- willed agent is able to resist acting
upon her currently strongest desire and instead act in accord with what she
judges it best to do (80). This is possible since agents with the sophistication of
normally functioning persons can employ strategies like promising themselves
rewards for resisting temptation, or directing their attention to less desirable fea-
tures of the path more strongly desired, and can generally exploit less episodic
and more stable motivation to exercise self- control. In so doing, they can bring
their motivational condition into line with their best judgments (81–3).
According to Mele, an agent can be both determined and exercise the
resources to act with self- control. Determinism is thus compatible with self-
controlled agency. But it is Mele’s contention that even an optimally self­
controlled agent can fall short of autonomous agency (1995: 121–7). For this
reason he concludes that more has to be added to his account of self- control to
get all the way to autonomous agency. Notice that, up until this point, Mele’s
theory appeals only to features of agency at work in the theory of action. These
include such notions as best judgments, strongest desires, intentions, the ability
to promise oneself rewards, the distinction between more and less episodic moti-
vational factors, and questions about the potential conflict between best judg-
ment and motivational desires.
How is it that on this view self- controlled agency is not itself sufficient to
capture autonomous agency? Because the beliefs, values, and principles that
inform one’s deliberation and conduct might be instilled in a person in some
autonomy- undermining manner. Such cases arise via various sorts of manipula-
tion, through brainwashing or hypnosis, or even a history of rigorous indoctrina-
tion during youth (recall the example of brainwashing mentioned above in
Section 8.1). The key element in an agent’s not having had, for instance, unshed-
dable principles and values instilled and sustained in an autonomy- undermining
manner is that the way in which the agent acquired them did not bypass an
agent’s critical capacities to assess the principles and values for herself (1995:
166–73). In non- bypassing cases, the agent had the opportunity to embrace or
shed them. Accordingly, Mele postulates a negative historical constraint on
autonomous agency: An agent acts autonomously if she acts with self- control,
has beliefs that foster deliberation, is able to deliberate effectively, and so long

Free download pdf