like them, then we are back with the puzzle of how and why we havethemin
response to“mere sound.”
Susan Feagin suggests a solution along Walton’s lines in proposing that in
reading with feeling we often simulate the emotions and feelings of the
characters we encounter. Perhaps what Walton calls the experience of
quasi-emotion is better understood as a matter of taking oneself to be or to
be in the position of the protagonist of a representation and so“feeling with”
that figure. Both in ordinary life and when reading,
One can shift or slide into a psychological“gear”wherein one uses one’s own
mind to model what another person does psychologically (the mental activity
that person engages in) under certain conditions. This [modeling] activity is
crucial to empathizing with actual people, and a similar phenomenon figures
importantly in those emotional and affective responses known as empathizing
with a fictional character...One empathizes with a fictional character, whom
I shall call the protagonist, when one“shares”an emotion, feeling, desire, or
mood of that character. The“sharing”...is donethrough a simulation, which
explains not only what emotion or affect one has but also how one can come to
be in the phenomenological state identified with that affect.^31
As in Walton’s account, the problem of how we respond with emotion to the
plights of nonexistent characters is dissolved. There are no such actual
characters, but we pretend that there are, and we further imagine that we
are they. We simulate their doings and feelings, and so come ourselves to
feel. The difference from Walton is that what we feel in simulating the
mental activities of fictional characters are, according to Feagin, real emo-
tions. Her account seems to capture much of what people mean when they
remark that in reading a fiction (or watching a movie or a play) they learn
“what it is like”to be another person.
But is Feagin’s account of what happens quite right? Do I, for example,
feel bitter vengefulness, masking my own feelings of a love I will not myself
profess, toward Cordelia, when she refuses to proclaim her love publicly in
empty clichés? Lear feels that toward her, and I am intensely interested in
(^31) Susan L. Feagin,Reading with Feeling(Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996), pp. 85–86,
81; emphasis added. Gregory Currie develops a similar simulationist view in“The Moral
Psychology of Fiction,”Australasian Journal of Philosophy73 (1995), pp. 250–59, and“Realism
of Character and the Value of Fiction,”inAesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection,ed.
Jerrold Levinson (Cambridge University Press, 1998), pp. 161–81.
210 An Introduction to the Philosophy of Art