An Introduction to the Philosophy of Art

(Marvins-Underground-K-12) #1
do thus identify with others, in both art and life, to some extent through acts
of imagination and imaginative attention. Following J. L. Austin, Cohen notes
that we do sometimes understand the emotions and thoughts of others, and
we do so not via introspecting them, but via an“act of imagination”in which
we“entertain...a metaphorical identity.”^51 It is, Cohen claims,

thesameachievement when we (i) appreciate a fictional narrative by
identifying with its characters, (ii) appreciate a work, narrative or not,
fictional or not, by identifying with its artist, where this requires imagining
oneself to be making those marks, or writing those words, or sounding that
music, and (iii) engage in genuine moral exchange, where this requires getting
a sense of things as felt by one’s opponent.^52

Cohen argues that“the ability [to think of oneself as another, whether a
fictional character, an author developing and attending to fictional charac-
ters, an implied or actual performer or composer of music, a painter develop-
ing a point of view, a historian, or an actual person in ordinary life] is a
fundamental human capacity without which our moral and aesthetic lives
would scarcely be possible.”^53 It is simply“a fact about human beings that
they respond” emotionally to presented situations, including ones that
develop over time, no matter whether real or actual,“perhaps a fact that is
in need of no special explanation, nor susceptible of any explanation.”^54
Cohen notes that one way to understand how I may both genuinely feel
something and yet fail to act or even to be disposed to act to change a
situation is that there is, given that I am reading a fiction,“nothing I could
do,”^55 just as I might genuinely feel something but be unmoved to act when
either reading about actual events in the past or watching actual current
events through a telescope or presented on television. In all these cases our
emotional responses seem both real and complexly sustained and developed
in our continuing attentions. Cohen adds that the interest of spectators in
bullfighting and of mountain climbers in ascending difficult peaks often
involves and even requires the thought that death is possible and sometimes
actual.^56 We do not seek only what is pleasant as an object of enjoyment, but

(^51) Ibid., p. 408A. (^52) Ibid.
(^53) Cohen,Thinking of Others: On the Talent for Metaphor(Princeton University Press, 2008), p. 13.
(^54) Ibid., p. 38.
(^55) Ibid., p. 36. Berys Gaut also makes this point (Art, Emotion and Ethics, p. 213).
(^56) Ibid., pp. 47–48.
216 An Introduction to the Philosophy of Art

Free download pdf