entreating him, but not for compelling him, or visiting him with any evil in
case he do otherwise. To justify that, the conduct from which it is desired to
deter him must be calculated to produce evil to some one else. The only part of
the conduct of any one, for which he is amenable to society, is that which
concerns others. In the part which merely concerns himself, his independence
is, of right, absolute. Over himself, over his own body and mind, the individual
is sovereign.^20
This is, for Mill, explicitly and exclusively a political principle. Othersmaybe
reasoned with, persuaded, and entreated, if not compelled. But Mill’s pos-
ition does explicitly rule out almost all censorship, unless it can be shown
(“calculated”) that direct harm to others does result from the production and
circulation of certain works of art. When the harm principle is politically
established and censorship is loosened, then it is natural to let a thousand
flowers bloom and a hundred schools of thought contend. Let each individual
judge what artistic works and moral values he or she favors, without worry-
ing so much about moral education. Friedrich Schlegel favored this kind of
artistic and moral experimentalism in arguing that“the will of the poet can
tolerate no law above itself.”^21 John Dewey argues similarly that
It belongs to the very character of the creative mind to reach out and seize any
material that stirs it so that the value of the material may be pressed out and
become the matter of a new experience...One of the functions of art is
precisely to sap the moralistic timidity that causes the mind to shy away from
some materials and to refuse to admit them into the clear and purifying light
of perceptive consciousness.^22
In a Deweyan experimentalist spirit and citing Nietzsche as a further precur-
sor, Richard Rorty urges us to follow strong poets, to embrace life and
libidinal energy, and to overcome our tendencies to small-mindedness and
fearfulness.^23 Engaging with imaginative art of all kinds is, Rorty argues,
(^20) J. S. Mill,“On Liberty,”in J. S. Mill,Utilitarianism; On Liberty; Essay on Bentham, ed. Mary
Warnock (New York: New American Library, 1974), pp. 126–250 at p. 135.
(^21) Friedrich Schlegel,“Athenaeum Fragments 116,”in Friedrich Schlegel,Philosophical
Fragments, trans. Peter Firchow (Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1991),
p. 32.
(^22) Dewey,Art and Experience, p. 189.
(^23) See especially Richard Rorty,“The Contingency of Selfhood,”in R. Rorty,Contingency,
Irony, and Solidarity(Cambridge University Press, 1989), pp. 23–43.
230 An Introduction to the Philosophy of Art