Thinking Skills: Critical Thinking and Problem Solving

(singke) #1

50 Unit 2 Critical thinking: the basics


In [1] and [2] there was a single premise and
a single conclusion. In the next passage
there is more work to do.
[3] Most spoken languages come in
many different accents and dialects.
They also contain colloquial, even
slang, expressions that vary from
region to region, or class to class.

2.7 Conclusions


The most important function of argument
analysis is identifying the conclusion. Once it
is clear what the author is seeking to establish
or justify, the rest of the argument usually falls
into place.
The kind of detailed analysis you have been
studying in the last two chapters is not always
necessary. If an argument is quite short and
straightforward, the conclusion often stares
you in the face. But with longer and more
complex arguments, it can be very easy – as
the saying goes – ‘to get the wrong end of the
stick’: to mistake a reason for a conclusion, or
an intermediate conclusion for the main
conclusion; or to misunderstand the direction
of the argument altogether. It is in order to
avoid this kind of misinterpretation that you
need skill and confidence in argument
analysis generally, and the recognition of
conclusions in particular.
As already noted in previous chapters, the
conclusion of an argument is often marked by
the word ‘so’ or its equivalent. Alternatively
the conclusion may be followed by ‘because’
(or some equivalent), to indicate that a reason
or reasons are being given to support the
preceding claim. In the absence of such
linguistic clues – and they often are absent –
we have to look to the claims themselves to
decide if there is an argument present, and if
so which part or parts of it express the
conclusion.
Here is a very simple example:
[1] The government won’t raise taxes this
close to the election. Tax rises are not
vote-winners.

In [1] there are two claims: the first is a
prediction, the second a claim to fact. It is quite

obvious here that the factual claim is being
given as a reason for the prediction; not the
reverse. It is because raising taxes is not a
vote-winner that the author is predicting that
the government will not do it. If instead we try
to say that tax rises are not vote-winners
because the government will not raise them, we
end up with something that barely makes sense.
However, this does not mean that the
second sentence couldn’t be a conclusion, in
a different argument. Suppose I were to
reason as follows:
[2] People say they want good public
services, but they don’t like it when any
more of their hard-earned money is
taken to pay for them. Tax rises are
simply not vote-winners.

Here it is perfectly reasonable to interpret the
first sentence as a reason to assert, and believe,
the second. In standard and abbreviated form:
People don’t like paying more (for public
services).

Tax rises are not vote-winners.

Activity

Free download pdf