The Philosophy of Psychology

(Elliott) #1

common-sense psychology, as such, nor upon any special features of the
case – rather, these are just cases in which the mind-reading faculty lacks
suYcient data to construct an accurate interpretation. So, if unwitting
self-interpretation can be involved here, it can be involved anywhere. Let
us brieXy elaborate.
As is well known in connection with split-brain (commissurotomy)
patients, information can be presented to, and responses elicited from,
each half-brain independently of the other. In the cases which concern us
both half-brains have some comprehension of language, but only the
left-brain has access to the language-production system; the right-brain,
however, is capable of initiating other forms of activity. When an instruc-
tion, such as, ‘Walk!’, isXashed to the right-brain alone, the subject may
get up and begin to leave the room. When asked what he is doing, he (that
is: the left-brain) may reply, ‘I am going to get a Coke from the fridge’. This
explanation is plainly confabulated, since the action was actually initiated
by the right-brain, for reasons to which, we know, the left-brain lacks
access.
As we noted above, these and similar phenomena lead Gazzaniga to
postulate that the left-brain houses a special-purpose cognitive sub-system



  • a mind-reading module, in fact – whose function is continually to
    construct rationalising explanations for the behaviour of oneself and other
    people. And it then seems reasonable to suppose that it is this same
    sub-system which is responsible for the confabulated self-explanations in
    the data from normal subjects discussed by Nisbett and Wilson. Indeed, it
    is reasonable to suppose that this sub-system is responsible forallthe
    access, orapparentaccess, which we have to our unverbalised thoughts. So
    if ‘inner speech’ doesnothave the causal role of thought, then it seems
    quite likely that there is really no such thing as conscious thinking. (For
    more extended discussion, see Carruthers, 1998b.)
    Some further indirect support for the ‘thinking in language’ hypothesis
    can also be derived from our discussion of the reasoning data in chapter 5.
    Recall that Evans and Over (1996) argue that human reasoning processes
    need to be understood as operating on two distinct levels – an implicit,
    non-conscious level, governed by a variety of hard-wired heuristics and
    principles of relevance; and an explicit, conscious level, at which subjects
    attempt to conform to various norms of reasoning. And recall, too, that
    this latter kind of reasoning is held to be crucially dependent upon lan-
    guage. Then we need only add that explicit reasoning may be conducted in
    sequences of imaged natural language sentences, to get the view that ‘inner
    speech’ is constitutive of conscious thought.
    It is easy to understand how some such two-level version of central
    cognition may come into existence, if we suppose that norms of reasoning


220 Forms of representation

Free download pdf