The Philosophy of Psychology

(Elliott) #1

has to chew on pretty hard to force himself to swallow. Tye, on the other
hand, believes that he is better oVin relation to this example, since he says
Swampman’s circumstances can count as ‘normal’ by default. But then
there will be other cases where Tye will be forced to say that two in-
dividuals undergo the same experiences (because their states are such as to
co-vary with the same properties in circumstances which are normal for
them), where intuition would strongly suggest that their experiences are
diVerent. So imagine that the lightning-bolt happens to create Swampman
with a pair of colour-inverting lenses as part of the structure of the corneas
in his eyes. Then Tye will have to say, when Swampman looks at green
grass, that he undergoes the same experiences as his double does (who
views the grasswithoutsuch lenses). For in the circumstances which are
normal for Swampman, he is in a state which will co-vary with greenness.
So he experiencesgreen, just as his double does. This, too, is highly
counterintuitive. We would want to say, surely, that Swampman experien-
cesred.
Some may see suYcient reason, here, to reject aWrst-order represen-
tationalist account of phenomenal consciousness straight oV. We disagree.
Rather, such examples just motivate adoption of a narrow-content ac-
count of representation in general, where contents are individuated in
abstraction from the particular objects and properties in the thinker’s
environment. Our case in support of narrow-content was made in chapter



  1. Given those arguments, it should be obvious that one could adopt a
    Wrst-order naturalisation of phenomenal consciousness while rejecting
    externalism.


3.2 Distinctions lost

This is not to say, of course, that we thinkWrst-order approaches to
consciousness are unproblematic. One major diYculty for such theories is
to provide an account of the distinction between conscious and non-
conscious experience, outlined in section 1.2 above. For in some of these
cases, at least, we appear to haveWrst-order representations of the environ-
ment which are not only poised for the control of behaviour, but which are
actually controlling it. So how canWrst-order theorists explain why our
perceptions, in such cases, are not phenomenally conscious? There would
seem to be just two ways for them to respond – either they can accept that
absent-minded driving experiences arenotphenomenally conscious, and
characterise what additionally is required to render an experience phenom-
enally conscious in (Wrst-order) functional terms; or they can insist that
absent-minded driving experiencesarephenomenally conscious, but in a
way which makes them inaccessible to their subjects.


Cognitivist theories 251
Free download pdf