c CUNYB/Clarke December, :
Descartes: A Biography
(iv.). While Descartes ‘strongly agrees’ with Seneca about that, he
also claims that Seneca’s proposal about living in conformity with nature
is rather obscure. It might mean following all one’s natural desires, even
though Seneca has already explained how such a policy could make one
miserable. The ancient philosopher must therefore have been using the
term ‘nature’ to mean something like the order established by God, and
‘living according to nature’ could then be translated, into Christian ter-
minology, as submitting oneself to the will of God (iv.).
This provides an opportunity for Descartes to comment on the con-
nection between the supreme good and the motivation required to seek
it. Descartes distinguishes among three different things in this context:
(a) the supreme good, (b) happiness, and (c) the final goal of all human
actions. Happiness is not itself the supreme good, but presupposes it,
because happiness is the inner contentment that results from possession
of the supreme good. However, one could think of either (a) or (b) as the
goal of all human actions. In one sense, the supreme good is the goal of
human actions, but the resulting happiness is the attraction that motivates
us to seek it, and it may therefore rightly be called the goal of human
actions.
At this point in their correspondence, Descartes’ letters and Elizabeth’s
replies followed so closely that the messengers who delivered them often
passed each other in opposite directions. Descartes accepted that some
illnesses take away the power of reasoning and consequently the ability to
enjoy the contentment of a rational mind.This led to a further admission,
that an indisposition of the body can result in a loss of free will. Descartes
draws the initially surprising conclusion that ‘it is worse to lose the use
of one’s reason than to lose one’s life’. The reason is as follows: ‘Even
without the teachings of the faith, natural philosophy alone gives the soul
reason to hope for a happier state, after death, than the one it currently
enjoys. It makes it fear nothing more distressing than being attached to a
body which takes away completely its liberty’ (iv.). This anticipation
of the pleasures of an afterlife helps to reinforce the distinction made by
Descartes between bodily pleasures and mental pleasures. The latter can
be as immortal as the soul itself on condition that they are based on reliable
knowledge.
This almost inevitable drift into dualism about happiness is qualified
bythe impact of the passions on the life of embodied minds. Descartes
distinguishes between pleasures that are exclusively mental and those that