MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
Heart, brain, blood, pneuma 123

natural philosophy, such as the so-called four primary qualities hot, cold,

dry and wet. By contrast, he adopted a predominantly empirical approach

to medicine, which in his view was tantamount to dietetics, the theory

of healthy living. His approach was based on insights into the wholesome

effects of food, insights that had been passed down from generation to

generation and refined by experimentation. He even went so far as to claim

that in reality physics does not form the basis for medicine, but medicine

for physics.

The question of to what extent a doctor should be concerned with, or

even build on, principles derived from physics (or metaphysics) remained a

matter of dispute throughout antiquity. What made the problem even more

urgent was that in many areas of controversy, such as that on the location

of the mind, it remained unclear to what extent these could be resolved on

empirical grounds. The doctor’s desire to build views concerning the correct

diagnosis and treatment of psychosomatic disorders such asmania, epilepsy,

lethargy,melancholiaandphrenitison a presupposition about the location

of the psychic faculties affected, which could not be proved empirically,

differed according to his willingness to accept such principles, which were

sometimes complimentarily, sometimes condescendingly labelled ‘philo-

sophical’.^10 This group of doctors with a profoundly philosophical interest

included, for instance, Diocles of Carystus (fourth centurybce) and the

author of the Hippocratic workOn the Sacred Disease(end fifth century

bce). They corresponded to an ideal proclaimed first by Aristotle and later

by Galen, namely that of the ‘civilised’ or ‘distinguished’ physician, who is

both a competent doctor and a philosopher skilled in physics, logic, and

rhetoric.^11 Caelius Aurelianus’ derogatory remark shows that this ideal was

by no means beyond dispute. Yet in this dispute, too, the variety of views

on the matter was much wider than his general characterisation suggests.

It is therefore highly likely that Caelius Aurelianus’ presentation intends to

exaggerate the differences in opinion between the doctors mentioned, in

order to make his own view stand out more clearly and simply against the

background of confusion generated by others.

These introductory observations may suffice to provide an outline of the

debate on the seat of the mind, which was the subject of fierce dispute

(^10) The first time the wordphilosophiais attested in Greek literature is in ch. 20 of the Hippocratic
writingOn Ancient Medicine( 1. 620 L.). The word is used in a clearly negative sense, to describe
the practice of scrounging from physics, which is rejected by the author. The name Empedocles is
mentioned in this context.
(^11) For this Aristotelian ideal see below, ch. 6 ,pp. 193 – 7. Galen wrote a separate treatise entitled and
devoted to the proposition thatThe Best Physician is also a Philosopher(i.e. skilled in logic, physics,
and ethics; see 1. 53 – 63 K.).

Free download pdf