MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
156 Aristotle and his school

the idea thatall(pantes) ‘extraordinary’ (perittoi) men are melancholics.

The subsequent discussion of the heroes Heracles, Aias and Bellerophontes

and the poets and philosophers Empedocles, Socrates and Plato shows that

the presupposition implied in the question is apparently based on a rather

specific notion of melancholy. Epilepsy, bouts of ecstasy, prophetic powers,

but also depressions, extreme fear of people, and suicidal inclinations are

all attributed to the same disease.^61 It is very important here to establish

clearly the actual aim of the author. Apparently, this aim lies first of all in the

explanation that this attribution actually has a physiological justification,

that is, that the very different, at times even contrasting characteristics

of the melancholic are all based on one coherent physiological condition;

secondly, the author intends to explain the in itself paradoxical connection

between melancholy as adisease( 953 a 13 , 15 :arrosth ̄ ema ̄ ; 16 :nosos; 18 :

helke ̄; 29 :nosemata ̄ ; 31 :pathe ̄) and the extraordinary political, philosophical

and poetic achievements (ta peritta) by means of this physiological basis.

This second aim has correctly been understood as readopting the Platonic

theory ofmania.^62 Yet whereas Plato, in his discussion on the origin of

mania, distinguished between divine enthusiasm and pathological madness

(Phaedrus 265 a), the Peripatetic discussion of this topic not only takes a

much larger range of mental and physical afflictions into consideration,

but also relates them all to one physical condition, and in the explanation

all divine influence is disregarded (even without fierce opposition against

this, as we find this in the Hippocratic writingOn the Sacred Diseaseand

in Aristotle’sOn Divination in Sleep^63 ).

Answering the opening question of the chapter is in fact only attempted

in the context of the second aim; the largest part of the text is devoted

to answering the other question of why the ways in which melancholy

manifests itself differ so much. The opening question is referred to on

just two occasions: in 954 a 39 –b 4 and, very briefly, in 954 b 27 – 8. This

division is also followed in the structure of the final summary of the chapter

( 955 a 29 ff.), which first recapitulates the explanation of the instability

(anomalia ̄ ) and the variety of aspects to the nature of the melancholic

character, followed by the summary of the explanation of the relationship

(^61) On a number of occasions, although never in a systematic order, these features are indeed associated
with melancholic diseases in the Hippocratic writings (see M ̈uri ( 1953 ) and the commentary of
Flashar ( 1962 ) on the particular occurrences).
(^62) Flashar ( 1966 ) 62 ; Tellenbach ( 1961 ) 9 ; Klibansky et al. ( 1964 ) 17.
(^63) See Tellenbach ( 1961 ) 10 , Pigeaud ( 1988 a) 51. Boyanc ́e( 1936 , 191 ) presumes that a certain divine
influence is implied in the role of thepneuma, yet there is no indication of this in the text of the
chapter (on the role of thepneumasee n. 68 below).

Free download pdf