MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
176 Aristotle and his school

(either perceptual or intellectual, and either ‘normal’ or extraordinary) in

sleep. But this question is not explicitly raised, and his relevant remarks

are scattered, nuanced and complicated, so that an answer unfolds only

gradually through the continuous discussion in the three works; and it is

not free from apparent contradictions. InOn Sleep and Waking, Aristotle

begins by defining sleep negatively as the inability of the sense faculty to

be activated (adunamia tou energein, 454 b 5 , 458 a 29 ). Sleep is said to

be a ‘fetter and immobilisation’ (desmos kai akin ̄esia, 454 b 10 ) an ‘inac-

tivity’ (argia) or ‘incapacitation’ (adunamia) of the sensitive faculty ( 455 b

3 ff.). It is a state in which the vegetative part of the soul gains the upper

hand ( 455 a 1 – 2 ), and it is caused by various physiological processes that

are connected with the digestion of food (such as heating, cooling, evapo-

ration of food, and sifting of the blood).^19 There is no sensation in sleep,

he says, because the central sense-organ, thekurion aisth ̄et ̄erion, which is

located in the heart, is affected by these processes and thus incapacitated,

and as a result of this the peripheral sense-organs (eyes, ears, nose, etc.)

cannot function either ( 455 a 13 ff.). Whether these physiological processes

also affect the ability to think and the operations of the intellectual part of

the soul, is a question which Aristotle does not address explicitly. Strictly

speaking, since Aristotle’s supreme intellectual faculty, thenous, is said to

be incorporeal and not to require simultaneous perception in order to be

active,^20 there is, at least in principle, no reason why we should not be able

to think while being asleep.^21 There are a few hints to this in the text, for

example inInsomn. 459 a 6 – 8 and 462 a 29 – 30 , which speak of an activity of

‘judgement’ (doxa) and of the presence of ‘true thoughts’ (al ̄etheis ennoiai)

in sleep, but it remains vague (see below).

Aristotle’s negative definition of sleep does not, however, imply a negative

evaluation of this ‘affection’ (pathos). Sleep is a good thing and serves a

purpose, for it provides rest (anapausis) to the sense-organs, which would

otherwise become overstretched, since they are unable to be active without

interruption ( 454 a 27 , 455 b 18 ff.). Here, again, one may note a difference

compared with thinking; for one of the differences between perception and

thinking, according to Aristotle, is that perception cannot go on forever,

indeed if we overstretch our sense-organs, we damage them; thinking, on

(^19) For a discussion of Aristotle’s physiological explanation of sleep see Wiesner ( 1978 ).
(^20) De an. 430 a 17 – 18 , 22 – 3 ;Gen. an. 736 b 28 – 9 ; see also ch. 7 below.
(^21) InDe an. 429 a 7 – 8 Aristotle mentions the possibility that the intellect (nous) may be ‘overshadowed’
(epikaluptesthai) by sleep, but it is unclear from this passage whether this is always the case in sleep
or only in exceptional circumstances.

Free download pdf