MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
Aristotle on the matter of mind 233

but whose existence, however marginal their importance may be, Aristotle

recognises as interesting and in need of explanation^89 – an explanation

which invokes the principle that even within the category of ‘what is con-

trary to nature’K3 1 -

Lthere is such a thing as ‘according to


nature’K3 1 -

L.


However much this may seem to be applauded, it remains unclear how

these gradualist and compensatory explanations should be accommodated

within the ‘normative’ theory ofDe an. 3. 4 – 8 , for in explaining all these

variations by reference to bodily variables he seems to grant physical condi-

tions a greater influence on intellectual activities than his ‘canonical’ view

of the incorporeality ofnouswould seem to allow.

To be sure, it may be asked whether there is actually such a tension, for it

might be argued that all instances of bodily influence on intellectual activ-

ity discussed above can be classified under the rubric of the ‘dependence of

the intellect on appearances’.^90 Yet even if this is true, we still have gained

a much more detailed view on how this dependence may work out in par-

ticular cases, what may go wrong in the supply of images to the intellect

and what range of bodily factors may actually influence this supply, and

indeed not only the supply but also the quality of images, and even the act

of thinking itself. Whether this affects the thesis of the incorporeality of the

intellect, remains to be seen.^91 One way in which it would not do so, is to

assume that the bodily influences only apply tolowerlevels of intellectual

activity such asdoxa(‘opinion’),hupolepsis ̄ (‘supposition’),dianoia(‘discur-

sive thought’), not tonous, or to ‘practical’ not ‘theoretical’ intellect, or to

‘passive’ not ‘active’ intellect.^92 This is a problematic solution because, as is

well known, it is not easy to see how the various terminological distinctions

between intellectual powers that Aristotle makes are related to each other,

and we have also seen that the passages on bodily influence do not seem

to be very specific with regard to the precise intellectual power they are

(^89) On all these phenomena, and their place in Aristotle’s philosophy, see ch. 5 in this volume,
pp. 164 ff.
(^90) This seems to be the view taken by most interpreters who have dealt with (some of ) the passages
I have discussed; see, e.g., Kahn ( 1992 ) 366 n. 11 onDe an. 408 b 9 : ‘In mentioning bodily change
in connection with thinking, Aristotle must be referring to phantasms’; Tracy ( 1969 ) 272 ff.; and
Verbeke ( 1978 ) 201 – 2 with n. 55.
(^91) See Aristotle’s uneasiness about this inDe an. 403 a 8 – 10.
(^92) See Kahn ( 1992 ) 362 – 3 : ‘It is not the disembodied principle ofnousthat requires phantasms; it is
our use ofnous, the penetration ofnousinto our embodied activity as sentient animals, which must
take place by means of the phantasms, that is, through the neurophysiological mechanism of sense
and the mental imagery of conscious thought.’ A distinction between
 
and seems
to be implied inDe an. 408 b 24 – 5 , although Aristotle is very tentative (cf. the use ofA)in b 29 ).
On different modes of thinking see also Lowe ( 1983 ) 17 – 30.

Free download pdf