MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
Introduction 17

of the question of sterility, a good example of the common ground that

connected ‘doctors’ and ‘philosophers’, in which thinkers like Anaxagoras,

Empedocles, Democritus and Aristotle himself were pursuing very much

the same questions as medical writers like the author of the Hippocratic

embryological treatise On Generation/On the Nature of the Child/On

Diseases 4or Diocles, and their methods and theoretical concepts were

very similar.

But Aristotle’s medical and physiological interests are also reflected in

non-medical contexts, in particular in the fields of ethics and of psycho-

physiological human functions such as perception, memory, thinking,

imagination, dreaming and desire. Thus his concept of melancholy (ch. 5 )

presents a striking case study of an originally medical notion that is sig-

nificantly transformed and applied to a completely new context, namely

Aristotle’s analysis of the physical causes of exceptional human success or

hopeless failure, both in psychological and in ethical contexts. In the case

of Aristotle’s theory of sleep and dreams, too, there was a medical tradition

preceding him, which he explicitly acknowledges; but as we will see in

chapter 6 , his willingness to accommodate the phenomena observed both

by himself and by doctors and other thinkers before him brings him into

difficulties with his own theoretical presuppositions. A similar picture is

provided by the psychology and pathology of rational thinking (ch. 7 ), an

area in which Aristotle recognises the role of bodily factors in the workings

of the human intellect and where, again, an appreciation of the medical

background of these ideas is helpful to our understanding of Aristotle’s

own position. And, moving to the domain of ethics, there is a very in-

triguing chapter in theEudemian Ethics, in which Aristotle tries to give an

explanation for the phenomenon of ‘good fortune’ (eutuchia), a kind of

luck which makes specific types of people successful in areas in which they

have no particular rational competence (ch. 8 ). Aristotle tackles here a phe-

nomenon which, just like epilepsy inOn the Sacred Disease, was sometimes

attributed to divine intervention but which Aristotle tries to relate to the

human soul and especially to that part of the soul that is in some sort of

intuitive, instinctive way connected with the humanphusis– the peculiar

psycho-physical make-up of an individual. Thus we find a ‘naturalisation’

very similar to what we get in his discussion ofOn Divination in Sleep

(see chapter 6 ). Yet at the same time, and again similar to what we find

inOn the Sacred Disease, the divine aspect of the phenomenon does not

completely disappear:eutuchiais divine and natural at the same time. This

is a remarkable move for Aristotle to make, and it can be better understood

against the background of the arguments of the medical writers. Moreover,
Free download pdf