MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
24 Medicine and Philosophy in Classical Antiquity

title of ‘younger Hippocrates’ or deemed ‘second in age and fame to Hip-

pocrates’. He practised in the fourth centurybce, and although we know

very little of his life, we can safely assume that he was one of the most promi-

nent medical thinkers of antiquity.^29 His interests ranged widely, and he is

reported to have written at least twenty works (some of them in at least four

books) on a great variety of areas such as anatomy, physiology, digestion,

fevers, prognostics, pathology, therapeutics, bandages, gynaecology, embry-

ology, surgery, dietetics, hygiene and regimen in health, foods, wines, herbs,

vegetables, olive oil, drugs, poisons, sexuality, and possibly also mineralogy

and meteorology. He clearly had a keen interest in ‘the phenomena’ and in

the practical aspects of medical care, and he rated the results of long-term

medical experience very highly. Yet at the same time Diocles was known for

his theoretical and philosophical outlook and for his tendency to build his

medical views on a general theory of nature. There are good reasons to be-

lieve that he was well in touch with the medical and philosophical thinkers

of his time, that he knew a number of the Hippocratic writings and that

he was familiar with, and to, Aristotle and Theophrastus. Furthermore, he

appears to have positioned himself prominently in the intellectual debates

of the fourth century, and to have played a major role in the communica-

tion of medical views and precepts to wider audiences in Greek society by

means of highly civilised literary writings in the Attic dialect. The basis for

his fame may lie partly in the impressive range of subjects he dealt with,

the almost encyclopaedic coverage of the subject of medicine and allied

sciences such as botany, biology, and possibly mineralogy and meteorology,

the considerable size of his literary production and the stylistic elegance his

work displayed. But a further possible reason may have been Diocles’ philo-

sophical and theoretical orientation and his tendency to relate his medical

views to more general theoretical views on nature (see frs. 61 , 63 , 64 ),^30 just

like the ‘Hippocrates’ referred to by Socrates in the well-known passage

in Plato’sPhaedrus( 270 c–d). For from the remains of his work Diocles

emerges as a very self-conscious scientist with a keen awareness of ques-

tions of methodology, a fundamental belief that treatment of a particular

part of the body cannot be effective without taking account of the body

as a whole (fr. 61 ) and of the essence of disease (fr. 63 ), and a strong desire

for systematisation of medical knowledge. Diocles’ use of notions such as

pneuma, humours and elementary qualities, his use of inference from signs

(^29) For a collection and discussion of the evidence and an account of Diocles’ views and historical
importance see van der Eijk ( 2000 a) and ( 2001 a), from which the following paragraph is adapted.
(^30) References to Diocles’ fragments are according to the numeration in van der Eijk ( 2000 a).

Free download pdf