MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
34 Medicine and Philosophy in Classical Antiquity

comprehensive systematic account), intended audience (e.g. specialists or

laymen), occasion (e.g. oral performance or written communication), and

so on. Thus it has been attempted to relate varying degrees of philosophical

sophistication in some of Plato’s dialogues to differences between the au-

diences for whom they were intended (as indicated by the contribution of

the interlocutors),^41 and something similar has been attempted with regard

to differences in method – and to some extent also doctrine – between the

three treatises on ethics preserved in the Aristotelian Corpus.^42 Likewise,

in some cases apparent inconsistencies in one and the same Aristotelian

work can better be accounted for on the assumption of a didactic strategy

of the work and a ‘progressive character of the exposition’,^43 whereby the

reader is psychagogically led to a number of new insights, which may be

refinements or indeed modifications of views put forward in an earlier stage

of the treatise.

Similar formal characteristics of medical and philosophical texts affecting

the interpretation or evaluation of particular passages and their relation

to other passages in the same work or in other works lie in the field of

‘genre’, where, again, the sheer variety in forms of expression is particularly

striking. When, how and for what purposes prose came to be used for

the transmission of knowledge in the late sixth centurybceand why

some writers (such as Parmenides and Empedocles, or in later times Aratus

and Nicander) preferred to write in verse when prose was available as an

alternative, is not in all cases easy to say. Yet the Hippocratic Corpus provides

opportunities to gain some idea of the process of text-production and genre-

formation, and one can argue that medicine has played a decisive role in

the formation of scientific literature.

The variety of forms of writing referred to above is manifest already

within the Hippocratic Corpus itself. Some works (e.g. most of the

gynaecological texts) show hardly any organisation and present themselves

as seemingly unstructured catalogues of symptoms, prescriptions, recipes,

and suchlike, though in some cases (e.g.Epidemicsbooks 1 and 3 ) this

lack of structure is only apparent. Other works, however (e.g.Airs, Waters,

Places; On the Sacred Disease;On the Nature of Man), show a degree of care

and elaboration on account of which they deserve a much more prominent

place than they now occupy in chapters on prose in Greek literature.

The Corpus Aristotelicum presents different problems. Here we do have

a large body of texts generally agreed to be by one author (although there

(^41) Rowe ( 1992 ).
(^42) For a summary of this discussion see Flashar ( 1983 ) 244 ; see also Lengen ( 2002 ).
(^43) Kahn ( 1966 ) 56.

Free download pdf