MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
Introduction 35

is disagreement about the authenticity of some of them). Yet any general

account of Aristotle’s philosophy is bound to begin with a discussion of the

problems posed by the form and status of his writings. Do they represent the

‘lecture notes’ written by Aristotle himself on the basis of which he presented

his oral teaching? Or are they to be taken as the ‘minutes’ or ‘verbatims’ of his

oral teaching as written down by his pupils? Certainly, some characteristics

of his works may be interpreted as evidence of oral presentation;^44 and with

some (parts) of his works it is not easy to imagine how they might have

been understood without additional oral elucidation – although this may

be a case of our underestimating the abilities of his then audience and an

extrapolation of our own difficulties in understanding his work. However,

other parts of his work are certainly far too elaborate to assume such a

procedure.^45 Some works display a careful structure of argumentation which

may well be understood by reference to an audience which is supposed

to go through a learning process; and certainly the ‘dialectical’ passages

where he deals with the views of his predecessors reflect a very elaborate

composition.^46 All in all, it is clear that not much is gained by premature

generalisations and unreflective categorisations (such as ‘lecture notes’),^47

and that we should allow for considerable variation in forms of expression

and degree of linguistic and structural organisation between the various

works in the Corpus Aristotelicum.

A further point that has attracted considerable attention is the relation

between orality and literacy. Although the details and the precise signifi-

cance of the process are disputed, the importance of the transition from

orality to literacy for Greek culture and intellectual life can hardly be over-

stated. Since the majority of the Hippocratic writings were produced in the

late fifth and early fourth centuriesbce, the Corpus testifies in a variety of

ways to this transition. Thus it can safely be assumed that several treatises,

especially the older gynaecological worksOn Diseases of WomenandOn

the Nature of the Woman, which contain long catalogues of prescriptions

and recipes, preserve traditional knowledge which has been transmitted

orally over a number of generations. Moreover, several treatises explicitly

refer to oral presentations of medical knowledge, such as the author ofOn

(^44) For examples see F ̈ollinger ( 1993 ) and van der Eijk ( 1994 ) 97 ; for direct references to the teaching
situation see Bod ́eus ( ̈ 1993 ) 83 – 96.
(^45) E.g.Metaphysics 1. 1 orNicomachean Ethics(Eth. Nic.) 4. 3 ; for other examples see Schutrumpf ( ̈ 1989 )
and Lengen ( 2002 ).
(^46) E.g.Generation of Animals 1. 17 – 18.
(^47) On the problems inherent in this notion see Sch ̈utrumpf ( 1989 ) 178 – 80 with notes 12 , 13 , 17 , 23 and
26.

Free download pdf