MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
On the Sacred Disease 61

However, this extrapolation of a ‘theology’ from the statements about

the divine character of the disease presupposes three generalisations which

are in themselves questionable, and which appear to be inconsistent with

other assertions in the treatise. First, it is ignored that there is a difference

between calling a particular phenomenon ‘divine’ in virtue of a certain

aspect or characteristic, and speaking about ‘the divine’ (to theion)ina

general and abstract way. As a result, it is tacitly assumed that by defining

the divine character of the disease as its being caused by natural factors (or

as its having a nature) the author implicitly confines the range of the divine

to nature or to the regularity which natural phenomena show (as if he not

only said ‘Nature is divine’, but also ‘The divine is identical with nature’).

Not only is such a generalisation of the use of the wordtheiosdangerous in

itself, but it also lacks any textual justification, for in none of the ‘positive’

statements does the writer use the expressionto theionin an abstract way.

In fact, the only instances of this use ofto theionare 1. 25 ( 6. 358 L.), 1. 27

( 6. 358 L.), 1. 31 ( 6. 360 L.) and 1. 45 ( 6. 364 L.), where the expression seems

equivalent tohoi theoi(‘the gods’).^39

Secondly, it is assumed that what the writer says about the divine charac-

ter of diseases holds of every natural phenomenon or event (‘natural’ from

our modern point of view, e.g. earthquakes, solar eclipses, etc.) and that in

his view all these phenomena show a similarly regular pattern of origin and

development and are therefore divine in the same sense as diseases.^40 But,

strictly speaking, the author ofOn the Sacred Diseasemerely denies that

epilepsy has a divine origin in the traditional sense (in whichtheiosimplies

theopemptos, ‘god-sent’), and he asserts that it is not more divine than other

diseases. This need not imply that all other phenomena are divine in this

new sense of ‘being natural’ (panta, ‘all’, in 18. 2 refers tonos ̄emata, ‘diseases’),

nor that a particular phenomenon is divine only in this sense. The author

leaves open the possibility that there are other things which may be the

effect of divine dispensation (in the traditional sense), for example divine

blessings, and the idea of divine dispensation or intervention as such is

nowhere rejected. We may even wonder whether the author really rejects

every appeal to divine healing, for in spite of his self-assurance concerning

the curability of the disease ( 18. 3 – 6 , 6. 394 – 6 L.), he admits that in some

(^39) For other instances of3  see 1. 4 ( 6. 352 L.), where the expression obviously means ‘the divine
character’ (sc. ‘of the disease’); 1. 11 ( 6. 354 L.) is ambiguous:3  may be synonymous with/
 , but it may also mean ‘the (allegedly) divine character of the disease’, as in 1. 20 ( 6. 356 L.) and



  1. 26 ( 6. 358 L.); in 1. 28 ( 6. 360 L.)3   (*is best translated ‘the divine character they talk
    about’: there is no question of meaning ‘pious’ here (contra Ducatillon ( 1977 ) 199 ).
    (^40) See N ̈orenberg ( 1968 ) 75 : ‘Insofern ist alles bis zu dem Grade gottlich, in dem es an diesen Naturge- ̈
    setzen teilhat.’

Free download pdf