MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
68 Hippocratic Corpus and Diocles of Carystus

the competitive character of early Greek medicine). To a certain extent this

may be viewed as an attempt to ‘secularise’ the sacred disease; and from

this point of view the positive statements about the divine character of the

disease may be regarded as reluctant or even derogatory concessions rather

than as proclamations of a new advanced theology. And from this perspec-

tive it can further be understood why the author states that epilepsy isnot

moredivine than the other diseases instead of saying that all diseases are

just asdivine as epilepsy.^56 For the purpose of clarity one might paraphrase

the author’s intention, with some exaggeration, as follows (differentiating

according to the two interpretations distinguished above): ‘If epilepsy is

divine, it is divine only in the sense in which all other diseases are divine;

well, the only divine aspect of diseases which can be discerned is the fact

that they are caused by factors which are themselves divine’ (interpretation

( 1 )) or, on interpretation ( 2 ), ‘the only divine aspect of diseases which can

be discerned is the fact that they have a nature’. As we have seen, on the

first interpretation of the divine character of the disease (which posits its

divine character in its being caused by climatic factors), this restricted con-

ception of divinity may well be connected with the fact that the influence

of these factors is rather limited (and with the use of the wordprophasis).

On the second interpretation (and on the reading-#C ’  , ‘in

this respect they [i.e. diseases] are divine’) the emphasis is on-#C: ‘it is

(only) inthisrespect that they are divine’. On both views the derogatory

tone of the statements can be understood from the author’s attempt to

mark off the boundaries between medicine and religion and to purify the

concept of divine dispensation. And it can now also be understood why he

defines the divinity of the disease only in those contexts where he tries to

point out the difference between the sense in which his opponents believe

it to be divine and the sense in which he himself believes it to be so.

This does not imply that the sincerity of the author’s statements about

the divine character of the disease should be doubted. Nor should their

relationship with developments in natural philosophy and with other con-

temporary ideas on religion and the divine be questioned. It is precisely

the philosophical search for unity and regularity in natural phenomena,

the enquiry into cause and effect, and the belief, expressed by at least some

of these philosophers, that in manifesting regularity and constancy these

phenomena have a divine aspect, which may have led the author to assign

a divine character to the disease in question. But the danger of stressing

this relationship with natural philosophy is that we read into the text ideas

(^56) Contra Norenberg ( ̈ 1968 ) 26 and 49 , who ignores the rhetorical impact of these statements. In 18. 2
(       "
) the emphasis is on .

Free download pdf