MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY IN CLASSICAL ANTIQUITY

(Ron) #1
On the Sacred Disease 71

and who are to be worshipped in temples by means of prayer and sacrifice.

The text is silent on the author’s conception of the nature of these gods, but

there is, at least, no textual evidence that he rejected the notion of ‘personal’

or even ‘anthropomorphic’ gods.^61 He has explicit opinions on how (and

in what circumstances) these gods should be approached, and he definitely

thinks it blasphemous to hold that these holy beings send diseases to men as

pollutions. Diseases are not the effects of divine dispensation; nevertheless

they have a divine aspect in that they show a constant and regular pattern of

origin and development. How this ‘being divine’ is related to ‘the divine’ (or,

the gods) which cleanses men from moral transgressions is not explained.

The idea of divine dispensation as such is nowhere questioned in the text

ofOn the Sacred Disease. Gods are ruled out as causes of diseases; whether

they are ruled out as healers as well is not certain, since the text is silent on

this subject. As I remarked earlier, the author does not believe that epilepsy

can be cured by natural means in all cases: on two occasions ( 2. 3 , 6. 364 L.;

11. 6 , 6. 382 L.) he recognises that in some cases the disease can no longer be

cured. Of course we can only speculate what he would do in such cases, but

it does not seem alien to Hippocratic medicine to make an appeal to the

gods in such hopeless cases.^62 We have seen that the borderlines between

secular medicine and temple medicine were vague and that the relation-

ship between these was seldom hostile or antagonistic (see n. 47 above).

Nor is the combination of ‘natural’ therapeutic measures with prayers and

sacrifices unattested in the Hippocratic collection. Thus the writer ofOn

Regimenexplicitly recommends this combination, and among his thera-

peutic remarks dietetic precepts and instructions concerning the gods to

whom one should pray are found side by side.^63 Of course, we should be-

ware of generalisation and not try to harmonise divergent doctrines, forOn

Regimenhas been claimed to reflect a religiosity which is rather exceptional

in the Hippocratic corpus and which is, according to one critic, ‘completely

different’ from that ofOn the Sacred Disease.^64 Now the ‘theology’ ofOn

(^61) Contra N ̈orenberg ( 1968 ) 78 , whose claim is probably prompted by the idea that this would be
incompatible with the ‘enlightening intention’ (‘aufkl ̈arerische Absicht’) of the author ofOn the
Sacred Disease.
(^62) This is speculative, since it is nowhere stated explicitly that in these cases the patient should make
an appeal to divine healing, though the case ofPrognostic 1 (see n. 30 above) seems to imply this.
But the recognition that in some cases medicine fails to help is frequently attested (seeOn the Art
of Medicine 8 ). On hopeless cases see Edelstein ( 1967 a) 243 – 5 ;Krug( 1985 ) 120 – 1 ; Thivel ( 1975 ) 60.
(^63) On Regimen 4. 87 ( 6. 642 L.): ‘prayer is a good thing, but while calling on the gods one should also
put in effort oneself ’ ( 3 . & 
"!Q   .  (3  <  R  R

 
); cf. 89. 14 ( 6. 652 L.), 90. 7 ( 6. 656 L.) and 93. 6 ( 6. 662 L.) (references are to the edition
of R. Joly and S. Byl ( 1984 )). [For a fuller discussion see van der Eijk ( 2004 a).]
(^64) Kudlien ( 1977 ) 274 ;cf.Norenberg ( ̈ 1968 ) 77 – 8.

Free download pdf