Encyclopedia of Psychology and Law

(lily) #1
with respect to his occupation (i.e., objectively he was
not an FBI official) and his rights and duties associ-
ated with his occupation (i.e., objectively he did not
have the authority to commandeer a public transporta-
tion vehicle in the interest of national security). The
nature of these distortions impaired his ability to
judge correctly with respect to the action of taking
control over the bus.
This formulation lacks a conclusive opinion as to
whether or not the defendant’s symptoms at the time
of the offense satisfy the required predicate condition
(“he suffered from a mental disease”). Also absent is
any conclusory opinion that the symptoms categori-
cally did, or did not, relate to the criminal act in the
prescribed way (i.e., “he did not know that what he
was doing was wrong”). However, the formulation
does provide a plausible accounting of the relation-
ship between the defendant’s symptoms and the crim-
inal behavior, but leaves it to the jury to “connect the
dots,” so to speak, in a fashion congruent with their
collective social and moral intuitions as to whether or
not an individual so disturbed should be held crimi-
nally responsible.

Norman G. Poythress

See also Automatism; Criminal Responsibility, Defenses and
Standards; Forensic Assessment

Further Readings
De Pauw, K. W., & Szulecka, T. K. (1988). Dangerous
delusions: Violence and misidentification syndromes.
British Journal of Psychiatry, 152,91–96.
Dreher, R. H. (1967). Origin, development and present status
of insanity as a defense to criminal responsibility in the
common law. Journal of the History of the Behavioral
Sciences, 3,47–57.
Goldstein, A. M., Morse, S. J., & Shapiro, D. L. (2003).
Evaluation of criminal responsibility. In A. M. Goldstein
(Ed.),Handbook of psychology: Vol. 11. Forensic
psychology(pp. 381–406). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
Morse, S. J. (1994). Causation, compulsion, and
involuntariness. Bulletin of the American Academy of
Psychiatry and the Law, 22,159–180.
Morse, S. J. (1994). Culpability and control. University of
Pennsylvania Law Review, 142,1587–1655.
Poythress, N. G. (2004). “Reasonable medical certainty”:
Can we meet Daubertstandards in insanity cases?
[Editorial]. Journal of the American Academy of
Psychiatry and the Law, 32,228–230.

Slobogin, C. (2007). Proving the unprovable: The role of law,
science, and speculation in adjudicating culpability and
dangerousness.New York: Oxford University Press.

CRIMINALRESPONSIBILITY,


DEFENSES ANDSTANDARDS


Although the insanity defense is numerically insignif-
icant, it remains profoundly important to the criminal
justice system as the focal point of the ongoing debate
on the relationship between legal responsibility, free
will, mental illness, and punishment. The insanity
defense has substantially survived in spite of persis-
tent philosophical and political criticism. Its history
reflects a balance and tension between changes in atti-
tudes toward developments in psychiatry and psychol-
ogy and changes in attitudes toward criminal justice,
incapacitation, and the desire to punish. Probably no
other area of criminal law and procedure reflects a
jurisprudence that is so driven by myths as that of the
insanity defense. Yet only a handful of American juris-
dictions have legislatively abolished it.
Insanity defense issues have concerned the courts
and legislative bodies for hundreds (perhaps thou-
sands) of years. As the various tests have developed—
M’Naghten, irresistible impulse; Durham, the test
proposed in the American Law Institute’s Model
Penal Code (ALI-MPC); the federal Insanity Defense
Reform Act, diminished capacity—and as efforts are
made to limit the scope and use of the defense, either
by use of a “guilty but mentally ill” verdict or by out-
right abolition, it is clear that the symbolic values of
the insanity defense must be considered carefully at
all times. No area of our legal system has engendered
a more intense level of debate than the role of the
insanity defense in the criminal justice process. On
the one hand, this difficult subject is seen as a reflec-
tion of the fundamental moral principles of the crimi-
nal law, resting on beliefs about human rationality,
deterrability (i.e., whether the punishment of a person
whose profound mental illness leads him to commit
what would otherwise be a criminal act would serve as
a deterrent to others), and free will, and as a bulwark
of the law’s moorings of condemnation for moral fail-
ure. On the other hand, it is castigated by a former
attorney general of the United States as the major
stumbling block in the restoration of “the effective-
ness of Federal law enforcement” and as tilting the

Criminal Responsibility, Defenses and Standards——— 161

C-Cutler (Encyc)-45463.qxd 11/18/2007 12:41 PM Page 161

Free download pdf