Encyclopedia of Psychology and Law

(lily) #1
figure). Enraged by the jury’s insanity verdict, Queen
Victoria questioned why the law was of no avail, since
“everybody is morally convinced that [the] malefac-
tor...[was] perfectly conscious and aware of what he
did,” and demanded that the legislature “lay down the
rule” so as to protect the public “from the wrath of mad-
men who they feared could now kill with impunity.”
In response to the Queen’s demand, the House of
Lords asked the Supreme Court of Judicature to
answer five questions regarding the insanity law; the
judges’ answers to two of these five became the
M’Naghten test (1843):

The jurors ought to be told in all cases that every man
is presumed to be sane, and to possess a sufficient
degree of reason to be responsible for his crimes,
until the contrary be proved to their satisfaction; and
that to establish a defence on the ground of insanity,
it must be clearly proved that, at the time of the com-
mitting of the act, the party accused was labouring
under such a defect of reason, from disease of the
mind, as not to know the nature and quality of the act
he was doing; or, if he did know it, that he did not
know he was doing what was wrong.

There are three main features of this formulation:
First, it is predicated on proof that the defendant was
suffering from a “defect of reason, from disease of the
mind.” From the time of M’Naghtenuntil today some
finding of “mental disease or defect” has been a neces-
sary predicate for the insanity defense. Second, once
such a “disease” is shown, the inquiry focuses on what
the defendant was able to “know.” That is, the interest
of the law under this test is in the ability of the defen-
dant to “know” certain things. It is for this reason that
the inquiry is sometimes referred to as a “cognitive”
formula. Third, the M’Naghten test focuses on two
things the defendant must be able to “know” to be
guilty of a crime. One is “the nature and quality” of the
act that was committed. The other is that the act “was
wrong.” In both instances, the question is whether the
defendant was “capable” of knowing these things, that
is, whether the mental illness had robbed the defendant
of the capacity to know what “normal” people are able
to know about their behavior. The idea, in sum, is that
people who are unable to know the nature of their con-
duct or who are unable to know that their conduct is
wrong are not proper subjects for criminal punishment.
In commonsense terms, such persons should not be
regarded as morally responsible for their behavior.

This test has been severely criticized as rigid and
inflexible, based on outmoded views of the human
psyche, of little relation to the truths of mental life,
reflecting antiquated and outworn medical and ethical
concepts. Furthermore, the use of language such as
“know” and “wrong” was criticized as “ambiguous,
obscure, unintelligible, and too narrow.” Donald
Hermann and a colleague have argued, by way of
example, that the cognitive aspect of one’s personality
cannot be seen as the sole determinant of one’s subse-
quent behavior (and the basis of one’s ultimate criminal
guilt) because the psyche is an integrated entity.
Critics also maintain that the narrow scope of the
expert testimony required by the M’Naghten test
deprives the jury of a complete picture of the psycho-
logical profile of the defendant as the test ignores
issues of affect and control.
Nevertheless, American courts readily adopted the
M’Naghten formulation and codified it as the standard
test, “with little modification,” in virtually all jurisdic-
tions until the middle of the 20th century.

Irresistible Impulse
In a partial response to criticisms of the M’Naghten test,
several courts developed an alternative test that later
became known as the “irresistible impulse” test, adapted
from a test first formulated in 1883 by Lord Stephen:

If it is not, it ought to be the law of England that no
act is a crime if the person who does it is at the
time...prevented either by defective mental power
or by any disease affecting his mind from controlling
his own conduct, unless the absence of the power of
control has been produced by his own default.

This rule allowed for the acquittal of a defendant if
his mental disorder caused him to experience an “irre-
sistible and uncontrollable impulse to commit the
offense, even if he remained able to understand the
nature of the offense and its wrongfulness.” It was
based, in the words of Abraham Goldstein, one of the
leading legal scholars on the history of the insanity
defense, on four assumptions:

First, that there are mental diseases which impair voli-
tion or self-control, even while cognition remains rela-
tively unimpaired; second, that the use of M’Naghten
alone results in findings that persons suffering from
such diseases are not insane; third, that the law should

Criminal Responsibility, Defenses and Standards——— 163

C-Cutler (Encyc)-45463.qxd 11/18/2007 12:41 PM Page 163

Free download pdf