he termed legislative facts and adjudicative facts.
According to Davis, legislative facts are those facts
that transcend the particular dispute and have rele-
vance to legal reasoning and the fashioning of legal
rules. Although judges are responsible for deciding
questions of legislative facts, they very often are the
subject of expert testimony. For instance, the question
of whether juveniles are as cognitively competent as
adults for purposes of evaluating the constitutionality
of imposing the death penalty for offenses committed
before adulthood is a legislative fact. Such legislative
facts are decided by judges, typically, at the trial stage
and reviewed de novo on appeal. At the appellate
level, legislative facts are sometimes referred to as
mixed questions of law and fact.
Adjudicative facts, on the other hand, are those
facts particular to the dispute. In ordinary litigation,
these are the facts that drive the dispute. Examples of
such facts include whether the traffic light was red or
green, the presence or absence of a stop sign, or the
kind of weapon allegedly brandished by the defendant.
Adjudicative facts are within the province of the trier
of fact (the jury or, if there is no jury, the judge) to
decide. On appeal, in nonconstitutional cases, review
is deferential under the abuse-of-discretion standard.
The appellate standard of review for constitutional
adjudicative facts is considerably more complicated,
but in most instances, they are reviewed de novo.
The Monahan-Walker Model
Although the Davis dichotomy has been extremely
influential in providing a nomenclature that is regu-
larly employed by the courts, it fails to capture the
complex interrelationship between different kinds of
facts in actual courtroom practice. Monahan and
Walker refined Davis’s dichotomy in the context of
social science research, though their three-part taxon-
omy could be applied to most forms of expert evi-
dence. A basic difference between the Davis and the
Monahan and Walker approaches concerns the respec-
tive focus each takes to the subject. Davis primarily
focused on the nature of the legal question involved—
legislative-like decisions or case-specific adjudica-
tions. In contrast, Monahan and Walker focused on the
kinds of social science available to answer the various
kinds of legal issues in dispute. In this way, the
Monahan-Walker model is more finely tuned to the
relevant issues raised by expert evidence. In particu-
lar, their model takes into account both the science
available on the subject and the level of fact in dispute
under applicable law.
Monahan and Walker identified three levels of evi-
dentiary convergence between social science and law:
social authority, social frameworks, and social facts.
Social authorityrefers to social science research rele-
vant to the determination of legislative facts and thus
the formation of legal rules. According to their pro-
posal, social authority is analogous to legal authority
and should be consulted similarly. Hence, judges would
consider social science “precedent” (i.e., available
research) as presented through briefs, through argu-
ments, and sua sponte. The information found to be rel-
evant would then be incorporated into the judge’s
conclusions of law. Alternatively, in the Monahan-
Walker model, social science research might be rele-
vant to social facts (largely equivalent to Davis’s
adjudicative facts), in which case, after being deemed
admissible, it would be presented to the trier of fact
through expert testimony. Finally, social science research
might have relevance as a combination of social author-
ity and social fact. Monahan and Walker label this con-
cept “social frameworks.” In social frameworks, some
issue in the particular dispute is claimed to be an
instance of a social scientific finding or theory of gen-
eral import. According to the model, the judge would
consider and instruct the jury on the verity of the gen-
eral claim, but the jury would also hear expert testi-
mony on how the theory applies in the case before it.
Although the Monahan and Walker model has gen-
erally received positive recognition, by far their iden-
tification of the concept of social frameworks has had
the greatest influence. This impact has occurred
largely because of the fact that most social science
comes into the courtroom in this two-stage form. This
is so even when the two levels of the framework are
not explicitly set forth, as occurs perhaps too often in
practice. To illustrate the power of the social frame-
work concept, consider three examples: the battered
woman syndrome (BWS), eyewitness identification,
and predictions of violence.
BWS illustrates social frameworks in their conven-
tional sense, in that courts have always expected that
there is a general fact that had to be proved and an
issue as to whether the case at hand was an instance of
that general fact. In the traditional context in which
BWS is offered as proof, the defendant is a woman
who has killed her abuser under circumstances that
traditionally would not have qualified as self-defense.
This may be because she killed when the victim was
276 ———Expert Psychological Testimony, Forms of
E-Cutler (Encyc)-45463.qxd 11/18/2007 12:42 PM Page 276