THE ETHICAL FALLACY
155
appoints. Butwhen
we
are
familiarwithit,andhave
ceaseddesiringtobeshocked,thisisnolongerthecase.
Itscritics,infact,complainofthebaroquethatinit
theyencounterdeceittoooften;thecauseofthecom-
plaintisthattheyhavenotencountereditenough.
Morally, then.
Renaissance
*
deceit' is justified.
It doesnotfollow onthataccount
thatasthetically
itis always
equallytobe admitted. If
'
deceit' is
carriedbeyondacertainpoint,weceasetogetarchi-
tectureandfindstage
decoration. Thereisnothing
wrongaboutstagedecoration
;
in itsplace there is
notevenanything aestheticallyundesirable. It has
asoledefect: thatitfails—andmustfailinevitably
—
^togiveusahighsenseofpermanenceand
strengtly'
Butthesearequalitieswhichareappropriate,above
1'
allothers,in
a
monumental
art
;
qualities,therefore,
which
we have a
right to
expect in architecture.
Here,then, issomejustificationforthe theorythat
thedegreeofpretenceisimportant. True, itisim-
portant
aesthetically,
and notmorally,butit isim-
portant. Butthenthebaroquestylehadthe most
penetratingsenseof
thisimportance. Itrecognised
thatthelibertyto pretend
—
^which the
Renaissance
hadclaimed from thebeginning
—
^though
unlimited
inprinciple,mustbe
subjectinpractice tothecon-
ditionsofeachparticularproblem
thatthearchitect
might
undertake.
Itwasaquestionof
psychology.
The scope of architecture,
in a period as keenly