The Dictionary of Human Geography

(nextflipdebug2) #1

Comp. by: VPugazhenthi Stage : Revises1 ChapterID: 9781405132879_4_M Date:1/4/
09 Time:15:19:32 Filepath:H:/00_Blackwell/00_3B2/Gregory-9781405132879/appln/3B2/
revises/9781405132879_4_M.3d


may be wildly different in their costs to buyer
and seller alike.
When Simmel (1978) noted thatexchange
is one of the ‘purest and most primitive of
forms of human socialization’, he endorsed
the idea that a market is asocial construc-
tion. As Stanford economist John McMillan
puts it: for markets to work they must be ‘well
built’: the field of market design, accordingly,
refers to the analysis and pragmatics – the
purposeful building – of institutions for trans-
acting market exchanges. As McMillan says:
Market design consists of the mechanisms
that organize buying and selling; channels
for the flow of information; state-set laws
and regulations that define property rights
and sustain contracting; and the markets
culture, its self-regulating norms, codes
and conventions governing behavior ... A
workable design keeps in check transaction
costs. .. Transaction costs are many and
varied. (2002, p. 9)
And yet even in acknowledging these proper-
ties, it is not unusual to hear the claim from
economists that ‘no one is in charge of the
market’ (McMillan, 2002, p. 7). And to this
extent, as Vaclav Havel once put it, the market
‘is the only natural economy’. This, of course,
raises another meaning of market that is both
ideological and political (seeideology). In
addition to markets and market transactions,
there is the idea of ‘the market’, or ‘the market
system’ or ‘the free market’. It is an abstract
notion – abstracted from the actual inter-
actions and functionings of many different
forms of market – but one that arises in at a
particular moment – its modern founding
charter is associated with Adam Smith’sThe
wealth of nations– and it has a long and com-
plex history. Smith was fully aware of the fact
that markets had their limits, that government
provisions andpublic goodswere indispens-
able to the operations of markets, and that
markets left to their own devices could in fact
be destructive. And yet he retained the ideo-
logical notion that markets were natural –
rooted in human impulses to truck, barter an
exchange. There is, of course, an alternative
narrative. Even at the time of Smith’s writing,
his world was awash with the operations of a
distinctively moral economy that privileged
use-value above exchange-value (Thompson,
1991) and of claims for a just price. Popular
reactions in defence of an arena that was seen
to be beyond the market – the commons –
defined much of what passed as politics
(Neeson, 1993). At the very least, then, the

modern market was not so much natural as
the product of struggle. And it is a struggle
that is central to the operations of the market
in the twenty-first century. Theglobal com-
mons represent a frontier of contemporary
resistance to – and shaping of – the rules of
the market (Saad-Filho and Johnson, 2005).
The contested nature of markets – in the
details or their operations or as a utopian
vision – is central to any understanding of
economy, liberalism and modernity
(Harvey, 2005). Karl Polanyi’s The great
transformationand Friedrich Hayek’sThe road
to serfdom were both published in 1944.
Hayek, an Austrian economist trained at the
feet of Ludwig von Mises, but forever associ-
ated with a largely non-economic corpus
produced at the London School of Economics
and the universities of Chicago and Freiburg
between 1940 and 1980, is widely recognized
as one of the leading intellectual architects of
the neo-liberal counter-revolution (seeneo-
liberalism). Margaret Thatcher pronounced
that ‘this is what we believe’ as she slammed a
copy of Hayek’sThe constitution of libertyon
to the table at Number 10 Downing Street
during a Tory Cabinet meeting. Hayek’s cri-
tique ofsocialism– that it destroys morals,
personal freedom and responsibility, impedes
the production of wealth and sooner or later
leads to totalitarianism – is theurtext for
market utopians. Collectivism was by defin-
ition amaderather than agrownorder: it was,
Hayek said, constructivist rather than evolu-
tionary, organized not spontaneous, a ‘taxis’(a
made order) rather than a ‘cosmos’ (a spontan-
eousorder),an economy rather than a ‘catal-
laxy’, coerced and concrete rather than free
and abstract (see Gamble, 1996, pp. 31–2).
Its fatal conceit was that socialism (and social
democracy for that matter) admitted the ‘reck-
less trespass oftaxisonto the proper ground of
cosmos’ (Anderson, 2005b, p. 16).
The other half of Hayek’s project was a ro-
bust defence of Westerncivilization– that is
to say of liberty,scienceand the spontaneous
orders that co-evolved to form modernsociety
(‘Great Society’, as he termed it). It was a
buttressing of the liberal (unplanned) market
order from which the preconditions of civiliza-
tion – competition and experimentation – had
emerged. Hayek, like Weber, saw this world as
an iron cage constituted by impersonality, a
loss of community, individualism and personal
responsibility. But unlike Weber, Hayek saw
these structures, properly understood, as ex-
pressions of liberty. From the vantage point of
the 1940s this (classical) liberal project was, as

Gregory / The Dictionary of Human Geography 9781405132879_4_M Final Proof page 441 1.4.2009 3:19pm

MARKET
Free download pdf