Comp. by: VPugazhenthi Stage : Revises1 ChapterID: 9781405132879_4_M Date:1/4/
09 Time:15:19:38 Filepath:H:/00_Blackwell/00_3B2/Gregory-9781405132879/appln/3B2/
revises/9781405132879_4_M.3d
metageography ‘The set of spatial struc-
tures through which people order their know-
ledge of the world: the often unconscious
frameworks that organize studies of history,
sociology, anthropology, economics, political
science, or even natural history’ (Lewis and
Wigen, 1997, p. ix). The prefix ‘meta-’ implies
anabstraction, a concept that in some sense
goes beyond the term to which it implies, so by
extension a metageography is a conceptual grid
that structures how geographies are ordered.
These grids are cultural constructions, and the
emphasisLewisand Wigen placeonthefactthat
they are used more or less automatically and
unconsciously, without critical reflection, con-
nects the concept to that of ageograhical im-
aginary. ‘Meta-’ can also imply an umbrella
concept, and Lewis and Wigen focus their at-
tentionontheglobalscaleandtheconventional
division of the world intocontinents. But the
division of theglobeinto a mosaic ofstatesis
no less commonplace and taken-for-granted,
against which Beaverstock, Smith and Taylor
(2000) have proposed ‘a new metageography’:
a globalnetworkof flows between cities. dg
metaphor For Aristotle, a metaphor ‘consists
in giving the thing a name that belongs to some-
thing else’. Such practice is rampant inhuman
geography, as in other disciplines: cities are
plant biomes (chicago school), cultural
landscapes are texts, economic localities
are geological strata ‘layers of investment’ and
non-renewableresourcestake onalife-cycle.
While pervasive, some writers have criti-
cized metaphors for being ornamental and
obfuscatory. Plato said that they make ‘trifle
points seem important, and important points
trifles’, while Thomas Hobbes believed that
they ‘deceive others’, and in geography,
Harvey (1967, p. 551) argued that they ‘hinder
objective judgment’. In each of these cases,
metaphor was attacked because it resulted in
ambiguity: it is ‘a sort of extra happy trick with
words’, as I.A. Richards (1936, p. 90) put it.
More generally, such misgivings result from a
particular view oflanguage held by such
critics: that language should be transparent,
limpid and utterly dependable, all of which
are undermined by metaphor.
Over the twentieth century there was an
increasing recognition that language takes on
none of those characteristics (see, in particu-
lar, deconstruction) and, concomitantly,
that metaphors are an indispensable part of
both writing and theorizing. Metaphorical
use comes in two shapes and sizes (Barnes
and Curry, 1992).
Small metaphorsthat pepper individual writ-
ing and research are part of the very infra-
structure of language construction, an
‘omnipresent principle’ (Richards, 1936,
p. 92). Mobilizing them requires skill and
sensitivity, forming an important component
ofrhetoric, the attempt to persuade others of
the force of one’s argument by using tropes
such as metaphor (Lakoff and Johnson, 2003
[1980]).Large metaphors, in contrast, struc-
ture entire researchparadigms. Some, such
as ‘organism’ or ‘mechanism’, are so deeply
ingrained that they become ‘root metaphors’
(Pepper, 1942), whereas others are only tem-
porary, mobilized for a particular use and then
discarded. However long their durability, all
large metaphors operate through a process of
‘metaphorical re-description’ (Hesse, 1980);
that is, transferring meanings and associations
of one system in order to re-describe the expla-
nandum (the part of the explanation that does
the explaining) of another system. An example
is Isaac Newton’s metaphorical re-description
of sound in terms of waves. Metaphorical
re-description is ubiquitous, as well as ‘poten-
tially revolutionary’ (Arib and Hesse, 1986).
When Adam Smith coined the metaphor of
the ‘invisible hand’ to describe the efficacy of
themarket, or when Marx said ‘workers have
nothing to lose but their chains’, or when
Bunge (1966, p. 27) asked, ‘Why cannot ...
concepts dealing with exotic and dioric
streams be applied to highways?’ revolutions,
albeit of different kinds, were set in motion.
There has been sporadic interest in metaphor
ingeographysince the 1960s, when the pro-
ponents ofspatial sciencefirst discussed the
linkages betweenmodelsand metaphors (Hag-
gett and Chorley, 1967). Later, those who ad-
vocated a humanistic geography,suchas
Tuan (1978) and Livingstone and Harrison
(1981b), were drawn to metaphors because of
resonances with human creativity and meaning,
twin planks of the larger project (see also
humanities). Most recently, critical attention
has come from geographers interested inepis-
temology. Large metaphors sometimes carry
unexamined intellectual freight, resulting in
unintentional and sometimes contradictory
meanings. They need tobeunpacked,inspected
critically for their coherence, consistency and
compatibility. Doing so also means scrutinizing
their historical and material origins. Metaphors
require ‘worlding’ (Smith and Katz, 1993). tb
Suggested reading
Lakoff and Johnson (1980); Smith and Katz
(1993).
Gregory / The Dictionary of Human Geography 9781405132879_4_M Final Proof page 456 1.4.2009 3:19pm
METAGEOGRAPHY