Comp. by: VPugazhenthi Stage : Revises1 ChapterID: 9781405132879_4_N Date:31/
3/09 Time:15:13:08 Filepath:H:/00_Blackwell/00_3B2/Gregory-9781405132879/appln/
3B2/revises/9781405132879_4_N.3d
social differences such asraceorsexuality
are enacted through and disrupted by the
workings of a range of non-representational
modalities (e.g. Lim, 2007). However,
heavily influenced by Deleuze and
Guattari (McCormack, 2005) and work on
performativity(Dewsbury, 2000), the prefix
‘non-’ in ‘non-representational theory’ names
an attunement to moments of indeterminacy
and undecidability, in which new events
emerge to exceed and potentially disrupt
given orderings (although see Anderson
(2004) and Harrison (2007a) on boredom
and suffering for criticisms internal to non-
representational theory around how an atten-
tion to newness can downplay relations which
are, respectively, suspended and broken).
To work through the imperative and prom-
ise of non-representational theories, there has
been a nascent experimentation with research
methods, as well as diagrammatic and narra-
tive forms of presentation, that take as their
task to learn to witness the ongoing taking-
place of life as a composite of embodied prac-
tices.theoryis called here to act as a ‘modest
supplement’ to life that would enable new
forms of description – a move that has occa-
sionally sat uncomfortably with the intense
theoretical experimentation that has also
been a mark of non-representational theory.
Substantive work has begun, however, to
draw this set of theories into often disruptive
encounters with a range of sub-disciplines –
see, for example, Wylie (2005) onlandscape
or Horton and Kraftl (2006) onchildren’s
geographies. Taking the two commonalities
together, non-representational theory can
be understood as a style of engagement with
the world that, encountering a range of
non-representational theories that exceed
human geography, begins from the non-
representational dimensions of practice and
performance. ba
Suggested reading
Dewsbury, Harrison, Rose and Wylie (2002);
Lorimer (2005); Thrift (2008); Whatmore
(2002a).
normative theory A theory or theoretical
claim that is prescriptive, saying what ought
to be. The theory ofneo-classical econom-
icssays thatmarketsshould be competitive;
the theory ofmarxismsays that expropriators
should be expropriated. Whenever the word
‘should’ appears, a normative theoretical
claim is lodged. The contrast ispositive theory,
which is a claim about what is. Competitive
markets exist in China. Donald Trump is an
expropriator. Positive claims (such as these)
might be wrong but, if so, they can be scien-
tifically falsified by facts. Normative theory
is never falsifiable, and for that reason often
engenders sharp disagreement.
The use of the distinction is most associated
with economics. The early Cambridge econo-
mist John Neville Keynes (1852–1949) in his
The scope and method of political economy(1930
[1891], pp. 34–5) distinguished between posi-
tive economics, which is ‘a body of system-
atized knowledge concerning what is’, and
normative economics, ‘relating to criteria of
what ought to be and concerned therefore
with the ideal as distinguished from the ac-
tual’. Keynes made the distinction so that
economists could be scrupulously clear about
their role and status: when speaking of whatis
(positive economics), they were scientists, and
when speaking of whatought to be(normative
economics), they were policy advisors. The
two should never be confused.
Inhuman geographythe distinction be-
tween the positive and the normative was
found most often ineconomic geography
- not surprisingly, given its origins – and
connected with the period of thequantita-
tive revolution, when economic geograph-
ers most demanded criteria delineating
scientific work (positive theory). Ironically,
however, much of the location theory
seized upon and elaborated during that
period was normative rather than positive,
and so did not constitute science in Keynes’
terms. Location theory was underpinned by a
set of ‘ideal’ assumptions such as an isotropic
plain, transportation costs proportional to
distance, equal population density and per-
fect rationality. August Lo ̈sch, one of the
principal architects of location theory, was
perfectly clear about its normative character:
‘the real duty of the economist is not to ex-
plain our sorry reality, but to improve it. The
question of the best location is far more dig-
nified than determination of the actual one’
(Lo ̈sch, 1954, p. 4[1940]). But this motiv-
ation was rarely registered by economic geog-
raphers at the time.
In any case, the discussion became moot
as the very distinction between positive and
normative theory began to unravel from the
early 1970s. Olsson (1980), a former acolyte
of positive theory, argued that a mainstay of
economic geography’s scientific approach, the
family ofspatial interactionmodels, was
irredeemably compromised by value judge-
ments – ‘is’ disguised as ‘ought’. Similarly,
Gregory / The Dictionary of Human Geography 9781405132879_4_N Final Proof page 505 31.3.2009 3:13pm Compositor Name: ARaju
NORMATIVE THEORY