The Dictionary of Human Geography

(nextflipdebug2) #1

Comp. by: LElumalai Stage : Revises1 ChapterID: 9781405132879_4_P Date:1/4/09
Time:15:20:51 Filepath:H:/00_Blackwell/00_3B2/Gregory-9781405132879/appln/3B2/re-
vises/9781405132879_4_P.3d


scientific knowledge is authentic knowledge,
and denying validity to metaphysical (non-
scientific) speculation (see alsoscience). The
antecedents are Enlightenment thinkers such
as David Hume (1711–76) and Pierre-Simon
Laplace (1749–1827). But the term was first
invented, and the philosophy formally codi-
fied, by the French philosopher and sociologist
August Comte (1798–1851), and published in
hefty instalments in hisCourse in positivist phil-
osophybetween 1830 and 1842 (six volumes).
Subsequently, each future generation con-
structed positivism in accordance to its own
ends, frequently minting a new title, perhaps
the best known being logical positivism,
born at discussions of the Vienna Circle during
the 1920s (see alsological empiricism).
Six features characterize the different strains
of positivism (Hacking, 1983):

(1) An emphasis on the importance ofobser-
vationas the foundation for all (non-
mathematical) knowledge. Scientific
statements were to be grounded in im-
mediate and accessible experience of the
world, through the five senses (cf.em-
piricism). Such immediacy guaranteed
that facts were pure, untainted by theory
or value judgements; they represented
the world as it really was – incorrigible
and inviolate. In particular, for Comte
recognition of observation as the source
of knowledge was the culmination of an
historical process in which the errors of
previous eras, characterized by the (mis-
taken) dominance of first religious and
later metaphysical thought, were finally
overcome.
(2) A belief in either verification (using ob-
servations to prove a thesis), or its vari-
ant,falsification(using observations to
disprove a thesis). Verification or falsifi-
cation is undertaken formally, using
common methods and employing rigor-
ous techniques such as statistical infer-
ence to scrupulously determine the truth
or falsity of a statement.
(3) A conviction that causality seen inna-
tureandsocietyis nothing more than
the repetitive concurrence of one event
followed by another. Positivism rejects
the usual interpretation of cause reckon-
ing it obscure metaphysical baggage
(who has ever observed ‘a cause’?). The
alternative is a formulation tethered only
to experience, the constant conjunction
of observable events (‘If event A, then
event B’: seelaw(scientific).

(4) A suspicion of theoretical entities that by
definition are non-observable. Comte
said that theoretical generalizations
must always be regarded at best as mere
hypotheses, and logical positivists tried
to reduce all theoretical statements to
(legitimate) propositions of logic (an en-
deavour that ended disastrously). Even
the less extreme solution of ‘operational-
ism’, that tied the meaning of a theoret-
ical term to the empirical operations
required to measure it, unravelled given
the implication that each new measuring
instrument defined a new theoretical
term.
(5) A faith in the unity of the method allow-
ing positivism to be as efficaciously ap-
plied to the humanities and social
sciences as to the physical and life sci-
ences. This is known asnaturalism: one
method fits all, revealing Truth wherever
it is found. Comte envisioned the unity
as a hierarchy in which disciplines study-
ing more complex phenomena relied on
the laws discovered in disciplines con-
cerned with less complex phenomena
(Hacking, 1983), whereas logical positiv-
ists (or at least Otto Neurath) cham-
pioned the Unity of Science Movement,
which cast knowledge of any discipline
into the single mould of physics (the
monumentally conceived International
encyclopaedia of unified science was to
show how this was to be done, but only
two volumes were ever written: Reisch,
2005).
(6) The ardent denial of metaphysics (i.e.
propositions bearing on the non-
physical). Comte had no interest in meta-
physical meaning, believing that their
time literally had passed: now was the
era of positivism. Logical positivists were
just as extreme. A.J. Ayer (1936) titled the
first chapter in his logical positivist mani-
festo for an English-language audience
‘The elimination of metaphysics’.

Several of these six features have been found
ingeographysince its institutionalization in
the nineteenth century, although sporadically,
oftenonly tacitlyand never all at once. Before
the Second World War, Anglo-American geog-
raphy was not much of a fit. While the discip-
line defined itself in terms of the meticulous
recording of empirical observations, often
from the field, and so met positivism’s first
criterion, very few of the other criteria held,
or at least for the reasons given by positivists.

Gregory / The Dictionary of Human Geography 9781405132879_4_P Final Proof page 558 1.4.2009 3:20pm

POSITIVISM
Free download pdf