The Dictionary of Human Geography

(nextflipdebug2) #1

Comp. by: LElumalai Stage : Revises1 ChapterID: 9781405132879_4_P Date:1/4/09
Time:15:20:51 Filepath:H:/00_Blackwell/00_3B2/Gregory-9781405132879/appln/3B2/re-
vises/9781405132879_4_P.3d


For example, while geographers during this
period were sceptical of theory, it was not
because they were persuaded by philosophical
arguments about the non-translation of an
observation vocabulary into a theoretical one,
but because theory implied a level of general-
ization that was deemed inappropriate to geo-
graphical subject matter (cf.exceptionalism).
The advent of thequantitative revolu-
tionin the late 1950s made positivism much
more relevant to geography. Empirical obser-
vations continued to be central, although they
were now often observations made by others
and recorded in thickcensusvolumes or on
drums of magnetic tape (thereby shifting
much geographical empirical enquiry from
the field to the desk). Verification became a
definitive pursuit undertaken using a set of
ever more sophisticated formal statistical tech-
niques (seequantitative methods). Constant
conjunctions were pursued, and Tobler
(1970) announced the First Law of
Geography: ‘Everything is related to every-
thing else, but near things are more related
than distant things.’ Positivism’s fourth fea-
ture, suspicion towards theoretical terms, did
not apply. Geography’s quantitative revolu-
tionaries were besotted by theory. In fact, the
revolution had been primarily a theoretical
one, especially ineconomic geographyand
urban geography, which were transformed
by importation of second-hand theory from
physics, economics and sociology. The pro-
spect of a unified method, however, was one
of the quantitative revolution’s strongest sell-
ing points.physical geographyandhuman
geographywould share a common language,
and geographical science would be at one
rather than a house divided. Finally, quantita-
tive revolutionaries prosecuted less the open
warfare on metaphysics that positivist philo-
sophers urged than a continual undertone of
carping about the need for greater precision,
less vagueness and the importance of the
exclusion of value judgements (seenormative
theory).
All of this said, there were few explicit dis-
cussions of positivism as such until it was on
the way out. Morrill (1993, p. 443), one of the
pioneers of the quantitative revolution, said he
‘never met a positivist’. And even Harvey’s
(1969) methodological compendium for sci-
entific geography,Explanation in geography,
barely used the word (it does not appear in
the index), preferring instead ‘scientific
method’. The quantitative revolution was
much more about getting on with the tasks of
theoretical development and application, or

crunching large data sets, than philosophizing
about what was being done in the name of
positivism. As a result, when some human
geographers later vigorously attacked positiv-
ism, it did not necessarily undermine the prac-
tices of quantitative revolutionaries and spatial
analysts, because the latter often neither knew
nor deployed the full array of positivist tenets
to begin with.
The critique of positivism was long and sus-
tained, and in many ways still continues. Each
one of the six features was criticized: (1) facts
do not speak for themselves, but are always
embedded in values, judgements and schemes
of interpretation (seeparadigms); (2) truth is
chimerical, and imbricated in larger social
relations ofpowerand knowledge (seecrit-
ical theory;discourse); (3) constant con-
junctions lead only to mindless statistical
exercises, and not to explanation (seereal-
ism); (4)theory should be central to our
enquiries, albeit not conceived as a mirror of
the world, but as reflexive, critical, productive
and provisional; (5) physical sciences offer no
privileged method, but are fallible, contradict-
ory, and limited by their historical and
geographical situation (see science); and
(6) metaphysics goes all the way down, the
lifeblood of our social existence and produc-
tion of knowledge (seeethics;relevance;
values).
These counter-claims amount to a reasser-
tion of the social foundations and responsibil-
ities of intellectual enquiry, and a refusal to
separate science from other discourses. Few
geographerswouldnowcount themselves as
positivist. Post-positivist geographies have:
dimmed the enthusiasm for unbridled use of
quantitative techniques; given a new slant to
areas that formerly were characterized as posi-
tivist, such as economic geography and, more
recently, geographical information sys-
tems; and opened up new fields such asfemi-
nismandpost-colonialism. In general, the
fall of positivism in geography undermined the
certainty and even optimism that the
Quantitative Revolution and spatial science
had promised, replacing it with what Gregory
(1994) calls a ‘cartographic anxiety’ (see
cartographic reason). Geography had
grown up. tb

Suggested reading
Gregory (1978); Kolakowski (1972).

possibilism A claim that human societies
may respond in a variety of ways to the influ-
ences of the physical environment. Possibilism

Gregory / The Dictionary of Human Geography 9781405132879_4_P Final Proof page 559 1.4.2009 3:20pm

POSSIBILISM
Free download pdf