The Dictionary of Human Geography

(nextflipdebug2) #1

Comp. by: LElumalai Stage : Revises1 ChapterID: 9781405132879_4_P Date:1/4/09
Time:15:20:52 Filepath:H:/00_Blackwell/00_3B2/Gregory-9781405132879/appln/3B2/re-
vises/9781405132879_4_P.3d


Massey (1993, p. 63) emphasized the politics of
mobilitythatderivedirectlyfromdifferentposi-
tionalities within a particular power-
geometry: ‘We need to ask whether our relative
mobility and power over mobility and commu-
nication entrenches the spatial imprisonment of
othergroups’.ForHyndman(1997,p.151),this
remainsapromissorynote,andMasseydoesnot
delve far enough into the economies of power
thatregulate, facilitate and disrupt transnational
movement. Although her argumentation-
sketches are often impressionistic and usually
operate at a high level of abstraction,
Massey’s later writings are nonetheless directed
towards the elaboration of what she calls ‘a
global sense of place’. For her, places are open,
porous and hybrid – literally, ‘meeting places’ in
which trajectories of all kinds (people, ideas,
commodities) collide – and to represent them
as containers, building blocks or objects (cf.
regional geography) is to foreclose the possi-
bilities of an intrinsically spatial politics. This
openness is not a peculiarity of modernglobal-
izationand cannot be reduced to the choreog-
raphyofcontemporarycapitalism.Overthelong
term, she proposes, different places have been
drawn into engagement with one another in ‘a
power-geometry of intersecting trajectories’
(Massey, 2005, p. 64), but there is no single,
plenary narrative withinwhich these can becon-
vened (p. 82); the outcomes of these intersec-
tionshavealwaysbeenopen-ended(thoughnot,
of course, unconstrained) because the spatial is
‘the realm of the juxtaposition of dissonant nar-
ratives’,anditisoutofthis‘throwntogetherness’
thatnewnarrativesaregeneratedandnegotiated
(pp. 140–2). Seen thus, power-geometries not
only shape and constrain mobility: they are
themselves in constant if irregular motion, so
that their analysis is necessarily both historical
andgeographical(cf.contrapuntal geograph-
ies). Place can then be recognized as ‘woven
together out of ongoing stories, as a moment
withinpower-geometries,asaparticularconstel-
lation within the widertopographiesof space’
(Massey, 2005, p. 131). dg

Suggested reading
Massey (1993); Sheppard (2002).

pragmatism An American tradition ofphil-
osophythat emerged in the late nineteenth
century associated with John Dewey (1859–
1952), William James (1842–1910), George
Herbert Mead (1863–1931) and Charles
Sanders Peirce (1839–1914) (see Barnes,
2008a). The movement is best known for the
idea that what counts as knowledge is

determined by its usefulness. As James
(1987, p. 578) wrote, ‘the true is the name of
whatever proves itself to be good in the way of
belief’. Pragmatism is thus a philosophy of
practical achievement. Ideas are labelled true
when they enable humans to get things done,
to cope with the world. After enjoying wide-
spread popularity in the first half of the twen-
tieth century, pragmatism fell out of favour
after the Second World War following the
ascendancy of empirical social science and
analytical philosophy, a narrowly conceived,
often technically abstruse form of reasoning
concerned with assessing the coherence, con-
sistency and precise meaning of an argument.
The publication of Richard Rorty’sPhilosophy
and the mirror of nature(1979) revived pragma-
tism’s fortunes, however. As an ex-analytical
philosopher, Rorty diagnosed with forensic
precision the pathology of modern philosophy,
prescribing as cure a large dose of American
pragmatism. Now found in a range ofhuman-
itiesand social sciences, the rehabilitation of
pragmatism is also a consequence of the wider
interest inpost-structuralismandpostmod-
ernism, movements with which it shares com-
mon interests.
James coined the name pragmatism in 1898
to describe the movement, but there were
always strong differences among its propon-
ents. At one point, for example, Peirce minted
his own neologism, ‘pragmaticism’, to mark
off what he was doing from his colleagues,
and sufficiently ‘ugly to be safe from kidnap-
pers’ (Bernstein, 1992a, p. 813). Bernstein
(1992b, appendix) usefully characterizes prag-
matism by five features:

(1) Anti-foundationalism, the belief that
there are no secure anchors either in the
world or in the mind that holds and guar-
antees the permanency of true know-
ledge.
(2) Fallibilism, the belief that no truth is ever
final, and that knowledge should always
be subject to further investigation, crit-
ical scrutiny, and questioning.
(3) Communal enquiry, the notion that
scholarship takes place within a wider
community involvingtrust,conversation,
and shared norms and responsibilities.
(4) Radical contingency, the belief, stem-
ming partly from Darwin’s theory of evo-
lution, that change is propelled by
chance and accident, that the only cer-
tainty is uncertainty (and for this reason
humans must always be ready to expect
the unexpected) (cf.darwinism). Peirce

Gregory / The Dictionary of Human Geography 9781405132879_4_P Final Proof page 577 1.4.2009 3:20pm

PRAGMATISM
Free download pdf