The Dictionary of Human Geography

(nextflipdebug2) #1

Comp. by: LElumalai Stage : Revises1 ChapterID: 9781405132879_4_R Date:2/4/09
Time:21:12:30 Filepath:H:/00_Blackwell/00_3B2/Gregory-9781405132879/appln/3B2/re-
vises/9781405132879_4_R-new.3d


monopoly rent, to raise rents artificially above
levels they would otherwise attain. Harvey ini-
tially applied the idea of monopoly rent to the
city, but it has been Smith who has systemat-
ically worked through a Marxist analysis of
urban rent. Key for him is the idea of therent
gap, which represents the difference between
the actual rent charged for a given plot of land,
and the potential rent that could be charged if
that plot was developed according to its best
use. For Smith, the rent gap is a result of the
inherentlyuneven developmentof capital-
ism. Only when the rent gap is significantly
large will it be filled by landowners and capit-
alists colluding in a process of redevelopment,
and producing maximum potential rents. Rent
levels are not the consequence of unfettered
market forces, but the deliberative power of
social classes to intervene and manipulate for
their utmost gain. tjb

Suggested reading
Sheppard and Barnes (1990).

rent gap The gap between the currentrent
on a piece of land (the ‘capitalized ground
rent’) and its potential rent under another
use (the ‘potential ground rent’). Developed
by Smith (1979c) and emphasizing capital
flows in the production of residential space,
rent gap theory is a crucial element of the
analysis ofgentrification. It suggests that
disinvestment in inner-cityneighbourhoods
reduces capitalized ground rent. When this
rent is sufficiently lower than potential ground
rent, opportunities for profit-making through
reinvestment occur, leading to residential
change. The theory has been criticized, how-
ever, for downplaying the role of individual
gentrifiers’ choices in shaping inner-city
neighbourhoods (Hamnett, 1991). em

Suggested reading
Clark (1995); Smith (1996).

representation A complex concept not only
because of the intricate disputes inartand
literature to which its traditional usage
refers, but also because of the variety of its
applications in modern and postmodern cri-
tiques of Westernepistemology(seemodern-
ism; postmodernism). At its minimum,
representation is conventionally defined as a
symbol or image, or as the process of
rendering something (an object, event, idea or
perception) intelligible and identifiable. Bring-
ing together the achievements of Renaissance
art (the ‘discovery’ of perspective) and

enlightenment language (scientific objec-
tivity, classificatory order), this ‘naturalist’
or ‘realist’ theory of representation is charac-
terized by the relationship between two
assumed metaphysical constants: the artist/
viewer (or universal, visual experience) on the
one hand, andnature(or the objects of exter-
nal reality) on the other. From this perspective,
the history of representation is the study of
constant mutations reflecting the increasing
sophistication of artistic execution in relation
to the changing appearances of the world.
However, morphology and advancing technical
expertise are not by themselves history: indeed,
‘history is the dimension [this understanding
of representation] exactly negates’ (Bryson,
1983). Recognizing this, representation is
analogous to what Edmund Husserl (1859–
1938) calls the ‘natural attitude’, a perspective
whose increasingly fidelity to a reality ‘out
there’ is as much a scientific and aesthetic
practice as it is an epistemological premise.
‘It is the aim of the sciences issuing from the
natural attitude to attain a knowledge of the
world more comprehensive, more reliable,
and in every respect more perfect than that
offered by the information received by experi-
ence’ (Husserl, in Heath, 1972). It is Husserl’s
student, Martin Heidegger (1889–1976), how-
ever, who most decisively equates representa-
tion with science/knowledge and posits it as
the foundation – and fateful flaw – of Western
philosophy. Manifest in what Heidegger
called the modern ‘age of the world picture’,
the representational model depends on the
construal of truth as ‘correspondence’ or
‘accordance’ (Heidegger, 1962 [1927]). Re-
presentation or ‘En-framing’ (Ge-stell) thus
not only assumes that the world is purely
‘present-at-hand’ (vorhanden), an object to be
submitted to our pitiless and possessive gaze,
but turns it into a ‘standing reserve’ for our
technical domination and habitual instrumen-
talization. What such an attitude forgets,
however, is that the ‘world is never [that] which
stands before us and can be seen’ (Heidegger,
1962 [1927]). Rather, true experience for Hei-
degger is a matter of ‘uncovering’ the hidden,
of revealing what might be concealed rather
than accurately and anonymously representing
what appears to be.
But if Heidegger’s indictment of representa-
tion suggests a phenomenological critique (see
phenomenology), other analyses insist on the
historical specificity of representation and its
implication in the production of knowledge.
For Michel Foucault (1926–84), representa-
tion not only has a history but a precise

Gregory / The Dictionary of Human Geography 9781405132879_4_R-new Final Proof page 645 2.4.2009 9:12pm

REPRESENTATION
Free download pdf