Teaching Critical Thinking in Psychology: A Handbook of Best Practices

(ff) #1

Scott O. Lilienfeld et al.


270


Educational and Assessment Implications

Before introducing students to these 10 reasons, it can be helpful to expose them to optical


illusions (e.g., the Muller–Lyer illusion, the Ponzo or railroad tracks illusion) to persuade


them that their raw sensory impressions can be deceiving (Hoefler, 1994). Such illusions


may help to disabuse them of naïve realism. It may also be helpful to provide them with


examples of how naïve realism has led to incorrect beliefs about the natural world, such as


the subjectively compelling belief that the world is flat or that the sun revolves around the


earth. In both cases, people’s raw observations misled them about reality.


Moreover, it may be useful to teach students about the long history of failed treatments


in medicine, including psychiatry. Most historians of medicine have argued that prior to


1890, most of the treatments (e.g., bleeding, blistering) that doctors prescribed to patients


were either ineffective or harmful (Grove & Meehl, 1996), even though most doctors were


persuaded otherwise. Similarly, most early reports of the “effectiveness” of prefrontal


lobotomies were based on surgeons’ informal observations of improvement. One early


proponent of lobotomy wrote that “I am a sensitive observer and my conclusion is that a


vast majority of my patients get better as opposed to worse after my treatment” (quoted in


Dawes, 1994, p. 48).


To assess whether efforts to teach students about the perils of naïve realism are effective,


one can present them with case examples of apparent improvement among clients in psy-


chotherapy, ask them to generate rival explanations for the reported change, and encour-


age them to develop research strategies that would produce more defensible evidence of


treatment effectiveness. If students can accurately identify these explanations and propose


ways of controlling for them (e.g., placebo-controlled designs), they are well on their way


toward shedding their naïve realism.


References

Arkowitz, H., & Lilienfeld, S. O. (2006, April/May). Psychotherapy on trial. Scientific American


Mind, 2 , 42–49.


Axsom, D., & Cooper, J. (1985). Cognitive dissonance and psychotherapy: The role of effort justi-


fication in inducing weight loss. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 21 , 149–160.


Beyerstein, B. L. (1997). Why bogus therapies seem to work. Skeptical Inquirer, 29 , 29–34.


Chambless, D. L., & Ollendick, T. H. (2001). Empirically supported psychological interventions:


Controversies and evidence. Annual Review of Psychology, 52 , 685–716.


Conway, M., & Ross, M. (1984). Getting what you want by revising what you had. Journal of


Personality and Social Psychology, 47 , 738–748.


Dawes, R. M. (1994). House of cards: Psychology and psychotherapy built on myth. New York: Free Press.


Eisner, D. A. (2000). The death of psychotherapy: From Freud to alien abductions. Westport, CT:


Praeger.


Grove, W. M., & Meehl, P. E. (1996). Comparative efficiency of informal (subjective, impression-


istic) and formal (mechanical, algorithmic) prediction procedures: The clinical statistical con-


troversy. Psychology: Public Policy and Law, 2 , 293–323.

Free download pdf