The Language of Argument

(singke) #1
9 6

cH A Pt eR 5 ■ D e e p A n a l y s i s

Suppressed Premises


Now that we understand validity and soundness, we can use those stand-
ards to determine which assumptions can fairly be added to deductive argu-
ments in order to complete them. If some extra premise is needed in order
for a deductive argument to be valid or sound, then that argument needs
that assumption in order to succeed as a deductive argument. That makes it
legitimate to add that extra premise to the argument even though the person
who gave that argument omitted that premise. The arguer did not openly
state the extra premise, but he did assume it.
For example, if we are told that Chester Arthur was a president of the
United States, we have a right to conclude a great many things about him—
for example, that at the time he was president, he was a live human being.
Appeals to facts of this kind lie behind the following argument:

Benjamin Franklin could not have been our second president, because he
died before the second election was held.
This argument obviously turns on a question of fact: Did Franklin die before
the second presidential election was held? (He did.) The argument would not
be sound if this explicit premise were not true. But the argument also depends
on a more general principle that ties the premise and conclusion together:
The dead cannot be president.
This new premise is needed to make the argument valid in the technical
sense.
This new premise is also needed to explain why the premise supports the
conclusion. You could have made the original argument valid simply by
adding this:

If Franklin died before the second election was held, then he could not
have been our second president.
Indeed, you can always make an argument valid simply by adding a condi-
tional whose antecedent is the premises and whose consequent is the con-
clusion. However, this trick is often not illuminating; it does not reveal how
the argument works. In our example, there is nothing special about Franklin,
so it is misleading to add a conditional that mentions Franklin in particular.
In contrast, when we add the general principle, “The dead cannot be presi-
dent,” this new premise not only makes the argument valid but also helps
us understand how the conclusion is supposed to follow from the premise.


  1. Every argument with true premises and a false conclusion is invalid.

  2. Every argument with a true conclusion is sound.

  3. Every argument with a false conclusion is unsound.


97364_ch05_ptg01_079-110.indd 96 15/11/13 9:53 AM


some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materiallyCopyright 201^3 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights,
affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.
Free download pdf