The Language of Argument

(singke) #1
2 6 9

D e c i s i o n s U n d e r I g n o r a n c e

As an example of partial ignorance, suppose that, just after graduating
from college, you are offered three jobs. First, the Exe Company offers
you a salary of $20,000. Exe is well established and secure. The next of-
fer comes from the Wye Company. Here the salary is $30,000, but Wye is
a new company, so it is less secure. You think that this new company will
probably do well, but you don’t know how likely it is to last or for how
long. Wye might go bankrupt, and then you will be left without a job. The
final offer comes from the Zee Company, which is as stable as Exe and of-
fers you a salary of $40,000 per year. These offers are summarized in the
following table:

Wye does not go bankrupt     Wye goes bankrupt

Take job at Exe $20,000  $20,000
Take job at Wye $30,000 $0
Take job at Zee $40,000 $40,000

Let’s assume that other factors (such as benefits, vacations, location, interest,
working conditions, bonuses, raises, and promotions) are all equally desir-
able in the three jobs. Which job should you take?
The answer is clear: Take the job from the Zee Company. This decision is
easy because you end up better off regardless of whether or not Wye goes
bankrupt, so it doesn’t matter how likely Wye’s bankruptcy is. Everyone
agrees that you should choose any option that is best whatever happens.
This is called the rule of dominance.
The problem with the rule of dominance is that it can’t help you make
choices when no option is better regardless of what happens. Suppose you
discover that the letter from the Zee Company is a forgery—part of a cruel
joke by your roommate. Now your only options are Exe and Wye. The job
with Wye will be better if Wye does not go bankrupt, but the job with Exe
will be better if Wye does go bankrupt. Neither job is better no matter what
happens, so the rule of dominance no longer applies.
To help you choose between Exe and Wye, you might look for a rational
way to assign probabilities despite your ignorance of which assignments
are correct. One approach of this kind uses the rule of insufficient reason:
When you have no reason to think that any outcome is more likely than
any other, assume that the outcomes are equally probable. This assumption
enables us to calculate expected monetary value or utility, as in the preced-
ing sections, and then we can choose the option with the highest expected
utility. In our example, this rule of insufficient reason favors the job at Exe,
because your expected income in that job is $20,000, whereas your expected
income in the job at Wye is only $15,000 ( 5 0.5 3 $30,000), assuming that
the Wye company has as much chance of going bankrupt as of staying in
business.

97364_ch12_ptg01_263-272.indd 269 15/11/13 11:00 AM


some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materiallyCopyright 201^3 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights,
affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.
Free download pdf