The Language of Argument

(singke) #1
2 8 1

sl i p p e r y sl o p e s

significant difference. U.S. Senator Everett Dirksen put the point memorably
when he said, “A billion dollars here and a billion dollars there can add up
to some real money.” To the extent that conceptual slippery-slope arguments
depend on this questionable assumption, they provide no more support for
their conclusions than do arguments from the heap.
Unlike arguments from the heap, however, conceptual slippery-slope
arguments do often lead people to accept their conclusions. Slippery-slope
arguments have been used to deny the difference between sanity and insan-
ity (some people are just a little weirder than others) and between amateur
and professional athletics (some athletes just get paid a little more or more
directly than other athletes). When many small differences make a big differ-
ence, such conceptual slippery-slope arguments are fallacious.
This fallacy is seductive, because it is often hard to tell when many small
differences do make a big difference. Here is a recent controversial example:
Some humans have very dark skin. Others have very pale skin. As members
of these different groups marry, their children’s skin can have any interme-
diate shade of color. This smooth spectrum leads some people to deny that
any differences among races will be important to developed theories in biol-
ogy. Their argument seems to be that the wealth of intermediate cases will
make it difficult or impossible to formulate precise and exceptionless laws
that apply to one racial group but not to others, so differences among races
will play no important role in sciences that seek such laws. Critics respond
that some scientific laws about races still might hold without exception even
if skin color and other features do vary in tiny increments.
Whichever side one takes, this controversy shows that, even if there is a
smooth spectrum between end points, this continuity is not enough by itself
to show that there are no scientifically significant differences among races.
That conclusion would need to be supported by more than just a concep-
tual slippery-slope argument. To show that certain concepts are useless for
the purposes of a certain theory, one would need to add more information,
particularly about the purposes of that theory and its laws. That is what de-
termines which differences are important in that particular area. Conceptual
slippery-slope arguments might work in conjunction with such additional
premises, but they cannot work alone.

Whenever we find one thing passing over into its opposite through a gradual
series of borderline cases, we can construct (a) an argument from the heap and
(b) a conceptual slippery-slope argument by using the following method: Find
some increase that will not be large enough to carry us outside the borderline
area. Then use the patterns of argument given above. Applying this method,

exercise III

(continued)

97364_ch13_ptg01_273-290.indd 281 15/11/13 11:01 AM


some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materiallyCopyright 201^3 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights,
affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.
Free download pdf