The Language of Argument

(singke) #1
3 2 4

C H A P T E R 1 6 ■ F a l l a c i e s o f V a c u i t y

Unfortunately, people usually do not make it so easy to tell when they
reason in a circle. Often, circular reasoning is disguised by restating the
conclusion in different words. Someone might argue that terrorists can’t be
stopped without torture, because, if you do not use torture, there is no other
way to stop terrorists. This premise means the same as the conclusion, so
this reasoning is still circular.
Another way to hide circularity is by suppressing the premise that repeats
the conclusion. (See Chapter 5 on suppressed premises.) Suppose someone
argues that terrorists cannot be stopped without torture, because they are so
callous that their goal is to kill and maim innocent civilians. This argument
depends on the suppressed premise that anyone whose goal is to kill and
maim innocent civilians cannot be stopped without torture. If terrorists are
then defined as people whose goal is to kill and maim innocent civilians,
then this suppressed premise reduces to the conclusion that terrorists cannot
be stopped without torture. So this argument is also circular.
Yet another trick is to put forward a statement first as a conclusion to be
proved, and then only much later—after several subarguments or tangents—
use the same statement as a premise on its own behalf. Consider this simple
argument:
The only way to prevent terrorists from committing their horrible crimes is to
inflict enough pain on them either to scare them off or to force them to reveal
information that enables the police to head off terrorist attacks. Because these are
the only methods that work, we cannot reason with them or talk them into giving
up. We cannot make friends or sign a treaty with them. We cannot buy them off
or satisfy their demands. Therefore, terrorists cannot be stopped without torture.
If the first sentence is supposed to provide a reason for the next three sen-
tences, then those three sentences cannot later be used as a reason for the last
sentence without the whole argument becoming circular, because the last
sentence, “Terrorists can’t be stopped without torture,” means pretty much
the same as the first sentence, “The only way to prevent terrorists... is to
inflict enough pain on them... .” Although this trick is often harder to detect
in a long and complex argument, such reasoning is still indirectly circular if
any premise in a chain of arguments repeats or restates the eventual conclu-
sion. Thus, we have circular reasoning if and only if one of the premises that
is used directly or indirectly to support a conclusion is equivalent to the con-
clusion itself.

Begging the Question


Reasoning in a circle is normally bad reasoning, but it is not easy to say ex-
actly what is bad about it. The problem with circular reasoning becomes
clearer when we notice that the same basic defect is shared by arguments
that are not strictly circular. Instead of arguing, “Terrorists can’t be stopped

97364_ch16_ptg01_323-332.indd 324 15/11/13 11:07 AM


some third party content may be suppressed from the eBook and/or eChapter(s). Editorial review has deemed that any suppressed content does not materiallyCopyright 201^3 Cengage Learning. All Rights Reserved. May not be copied, scanned, or duplicated, in whole or in part. Due to electronic rights,
affect the overall learning experience. Cengage Learning reserves the right to remove additional content at any time if subsequent rights restrictions require it.
Free download pdf