Cultural Geography

(Nora) #1
account. Rather than provide accounts of
distinctive regional material landscapes, geogra-
phers began to see landscape as residing within
the minds and eyes of beholders: landscape as a
way of seeing. Finally, in the mid 1980s geogra-
phers such as Denis Cosgrove (1984; 1985;
1987), Stephen Daniels (1990; 1993) and Kenneth
Olwig(1984), fired by the ascendancy of Marx-
ist and radical accounts of the world, particularly
those of Raymond Williams, argued that land-
scapes were material productions within which
were coded particular ideologies. Landscapes
were diagrams of power and influence that
helped to reproduce the very power structures
that produced them in the first place. In Daniels’
(1990) terms, landscapes were duplicitous in that
they could not be reduced to either their brute
materiality or the more ideological notion of
‘ways of seeing’.
Central to this potted history has been a criti-
que of thinking of landscapes as purely material
topographies. While there is no doubt that Sauer
had a broader agenda than the straightforward
mapping and description of different landscape
morphologies, it is equally clear that the major-
ity of work by his followers has been centred on
just such projects. To Sauer landscape was geo-
graphy’s naively given phenomenon. We often
forget that Sauer looked to phenomenology to
construct his view of the discipline. ‘Every field
of knowledge is characterized by its declared
preoccupation with a certain group of pheno-
mena,’ he declared, ‘which it undertakes to iden-
tify and order according to their relations’ (1965:
316). No other discipline could be said to have
landscape as its ‘object of consciousness’, and it
was (in Sauer’s eyes) the unique and privileged
role of geography to describe and understand
(which amount to the same thing in much of
Sauer’s work) this phenomenon:

The task of geography is conceived as the establishment
of a critical system which embraces the phenomenology
of landscape, in order to grasp in all its meaning and
color the varied terrestrial scene. (1965: 319)
Importantly Sauer was keen to emphasize that
landscape was not just a scene for the activities of
people but something which included the works
of people as a defining element. It was in this way
that Sauer rejected the determinism of his prede-
cessors, Semple and Huntingdon, and it is for this
reason that Sauer’s geography became known as
‘cultural geography’. Unfortunately the activities
of humans on the landscape became conflated
with the action of an overarching and superor-
ganic ‘culture’ on the land (Duncan, 1980).

Humanistic geographers inherited the concern
with the issue of landscape but turned their atten-
tion away from the ‘morphology’ of landscape
and towards the ‘experience’ of landscape. An
important link here is J.B. Jackson (in many
ways the hero of this story). Jackson followed
the Berkeley line in his interest in the cultural
landscape and his distrust of formal theory. But
Jackson also began to explore the ‘symbolic’
aspects of landscape:

[A] landscape is not a natural feature of the environ-
ment, but a synthetic space, a man-made system of
spaces superimposed on the face of the land function-
ing and evolving not according to natural laws but to
serve a community. A landscape is thus a space delib-
erately created to speed up or slow down nature.
(1984: 8)

Jackson recognized the importance of art and
emotion in the study of landscape as he attempted
to teach his students to ‘read’ the landscape as a
kind of text full of symbolic clues to the meaning
that lies behind the bare morphology. In this sense
his work influenced humanistic geographers, as
is clear from the long dedication to him in the
book The Interpretation of Ordinary Landscapes
(Meinig, 1979b). The overwhelming theme of
Meinig’s volume is the way in which culture
provides a lens to focus our idea of landscape.
The attention throughout is on the way we see
the landscape rather than what we see in the
landscape. Vision becomes the central way of
getting at landscape. Meinig’s well-known paper
‘The beholding eye’ outlines 10 views of the
same landscape which depend on the particular
way in which individuals with different interests
will interpret the same physical features.
We may certainly agree that we will see many of the
same elements –houses, roads, trees, hills –in terms of
such denotations as number, form, diversity and color;
but such facts only take on meaning through associa-
tion, they must be fitted together according to some
coherent body of ideas. Thus we confront the central
problem: any landscape is composed not only of what
lies before our eyes but what lies within our heads.
(1979a: 34)

The same point is repeated by Yi-Fu Tuan in his
essay ‘Thought and landscape’. ‘Landscape,’ he
argues, ‘is not to be defined by itemizing its
parts. The parts are subsidiary clues to an inte-
grated image. Landscape is such an image, a con-
struct of the mind and of feeling’ (1979: 89). To
many humanists landscape is an image. The
focus is turned away from the form of the mate-
rial landscape and towards the way we see

LANDSCAPE AND THE OBLITERATION OF PRACTICE 271

3029-ch13.qxd 03-10-02 4:53 PM Page 271

Free download pdf