Cultural Geography

(Nora) #1
THE CIRCULARITY OF
KNOWLEDGE

Culture and knowledge do not sit together easily.
Hence the need for a chapter on the ways they
relate to one another. The problem can be stated
simply: while every notion of ‘culture’ – especially
in a book like the present one – represents a
form of knowledge, this latter can never wholly
be separated from cultural influences. To define
‘knowledge’ is thus to enter a twilight zone of
sorts where success presupposes what it seeks to
explain. In this respect, the scientific analysis of
‘culture’ is no different from other forms of
scientific inquiry: it, too, is caught in a circle
where knowledge and its objects are mutually
constitutive elements. This chapter explores the
ramifications of the initial arrangement set out in
the preceding two sentences. It contends that
both the concept of ‘culture’ and its academic
pursuit can profitably be understood as attempts
to address the involvement of knowledge in the
workings of societies. In other words, ‘culture’ is
one key epistemological answer to the mutual
constitution of science and its objects and thus to
the problem of circularity that has troubled and
continues to trouble the (human) sciences.
To develop this argument, the chapter pro-
ceeds from a historical reconstruction of knowl-
edge and the problems that have traditionally
been associated with its constructed character to
the role of ‘culture’ in the attempts to create novel
and illuminating forms of insight. Already, this
may strike some readers as a highly contrived
setup for a chapter addressing the cultural side of
epistemology. And I would agree that we do not
normally perceive of knowledge in this manner –
as an object itself, rather than a condition. Still, it
is appropriate for a chapter addressing ‘the nexus

between culture and knowledge’ to be clear
about its own limitations. In fact, the impulse
itself that makes us seek clarity concerning the
boundaries to knowledge has been one of the
guiding principles of epistemology, the branch of
philosophy concerned with knowledge. Here
scepticism has arguably been central, at least
within the western canon of philosophical texts.
Such scepticism has variously attached itself to
the relationship between ‘understanding’ and
‘knowledge’ and that between ‘experience’ and
‘knowledge’, and arguably reached its pinnacle
in the work of the seventeenth-century author
René Descartes (Hookway, 1990).
We shall have numerous occasions to revisit
the emerging and quintessentially modern battle-
ground between the optimistic and pessimistic
views as to how best to break free of the circu-
larity at the root of epistemology – a circularity
that binds ‘knowledge’ to its objects without
allowing the latter ever to be independent from
the former. Before we do so, we need to make
clear that ‘circularity’ does not in and of itself
pose a limit to any kind of knowledge. Rather, it
imposes a no less important structural character-
istic. Recognizing this trait, we can say that any
attempt to delineate spaces of knowledge has to
address what is often merely implicit in many
other definitions of knowledge: the self-referential
nature of its constitution. To give examples here,
the uncritical invocation of ‘knowledge’ is rather
akin to the explanation of an apple through refer-
ence to an apple tree or the definition of a ‘thief ’
through reference to an activity called ‘stealing’:
one has to be familiar with the one to make any
sense of the other.
A still more fitting analogy would perhaps
liken the limits to ‘knowledge’ to the closed
reference system of a thesaurus or an encyclope-
dia, where in order to understand a definition a

28


The Culture of Epistemology


Ulf Strohmayer

3029-ch28.qxd 03-10-02 11:07 AM Page 520

Free download pdf