The Sociology of Philosophies

(Wang) #1
is someone who has produced an important discovery: the conception of
Platonic Ideas, the theory of evolution, the fundamental theorem of the calcu-
lus. These are the great accomplishments of the field; without them, there
would be nothing to teach novices or to broadcast for outsiders to admire.
Within the intellectual community, however, great truths are most important
if the community is in a scholasticizing mode, turned backwards toward its
own past. When the community is oriented toward innovation, great truths
are not so much an advantage as an obstacle. For if the truth is already
discovered, there is little or nothing for the intellectuals who come afterwards
to do; they can be teachers to the outside world, preservers and interpreters of
the truth, but not discoverers in their own right.
The paradox is that for an intellectual community to be in a great creative
age, it must be both making great discoveries and also overturning them, and
not just once but over and again. The most successful intellectuals tend to be
chained together across the generations. This implies that the cultural capital
of each one is built on the accomplishment of his or her predecessors, but also
goes beyond it in truly major ways. We are not dealing here simply with a
Kuhnian paradigm, in the sense of an exemplar of successful research. Such
exemplars include cognitive worldviews, which have already answered the
major questions. The work they leave to do, in a host of “offspring papers,”
is minor, routine, a matter of adding details to what is already known in the
large. Such work occupies the middle or lower-middle rungs of the ranking of
intellectual eminence. The cultural capital which consists of having learned a
powerful paradigm, then, cannot be the most valuable CC for one’s own future
success.
The most important CC is that which facilitates one’s own discoveries.
Above all, it locates the intellectual territory on which work can be done. It
does not merely solve puzzles but creates them. Fermat’s last theorem, tanta-
lizingly holding out the claim for a proof, is perhaps a greater source of fame
than his more definitive work; and it doubtless will have paid off greater
eminence for Fermat than for anyone who eventually solved it. (This seemed
to be the case when the problem was finally solved in 1994.) Great intellectual
work is that which creates a large space on which followers can work. This
implies that the imperfections of major doctrines are the source of their appeal.
But there must be greatness on both sides: great doctrines, great imperfections.
One reason why Plato was such a dominant figure in late antiquity is that the
ambiguities in his doctrine of Ideas led to many elaborations, and even to the
formation of divergent schools. His shifting theories of the soul, of immortality
and reincarnation, were one source of his popularity and fruitfulness. Similarly,
the Vienna Circle had already run into a major problem as soon as it was
formed in the 1920s; its aggressive emphasis on the verifiability and empirical

32 • (^) The Skeleton of Theory

Free download pdf