The Politics of the Environment: Ideas, Activism, Policy, 2nd Edition

(Tuis.) #1
Environmental philosophy

2.5 Conservationism and preservationism

Conservationism and preservationism were two
early currents of environmental thinking that
gave birth to the first wave of ‘environmental’
pressure groups in the nineteenth and early
twentieth centuries.
‘Resource conservationism’ refers to the
ideas of modern land management popularised
by Gifford Pinchot early in the twentieth
century. His doctrine of conservation abhorred
the wasteful exploitation of nature. Pinchot
commended the use of scientific management
techniques in developing land for the wider
benefit of society rather than for a privileged
few.
‘Preservationism’ represents an attitude of
reverence towards nature, especially for the

wilderness of the USA and Australia. Its leading
exponent was John Muir of the Sierra Club,
whose writings had a greater emphasis on the
interrelation of humanity and nature.
Both approaches were clearly
anthropocentric, although in preservationism
humans were not the sole source of value.
Conservation involves managing a resource for
later consumption whereas preservation will
protect a resource from any interference. Or, as
Eckersley ( 1992 ) puts it, ‘whereas Pinchot was
concerned toconservenaturefordevelopment,
Muir’s concern was topreservenaturefrom
development’ (p. 39).
See Eckersley ( 1992 : ch. 2) and
Oelschlaeger ( 1991 ).

explicitly traverses the anthropocentric–ecocentric divide by granting moral
consideration to non-humans. Yet animal liberationists employ ethical argu-
ments that have set them apart from ecocentric theory. In part this diver-
gence can be explained by the origins of the animal rights movement.
Whereas contemporary environmentalism is rooted in early conservationist
and preservationist movements (see Box2.5), animal liberationism emerged
from the separate animal protection tradition. Animal liberationists have
mobilised their arguments in support of vegetarianism, and in opposition
tohunting, the fur trade, modern farming practices and vivisection. The
animal liberation literature has focused on protecting individual creatures
(rather than whole species) by employing prevailing moral discourses to
argue that the moral consideration shown to humans should be extended
toarange of non-human creatures. The two main approaches within ani-
mal liberationism – utilitarianism and animal rights – are represented by
the leading theorists, Peter Singer and Tom Regan.
Singer ( 1976 , 1979)proposes a utilitarian argument in which actions
should be judged by their consequences, i.e. the pleasure or pain, happiness
or well-being they produce. He develops Jeremy Bentham’s observation that
todetermine which creatures should receive moral consideration, the ques-
tion we should ask is ‘not, Can theyreason?norCan theytalkbut,Can they
suffer?’ (Singer 1979 : 50). Singer argues thatsentience–‘thecapacity to suf-
fer orexperience enjoyment or happiness’ (ibid.: 50) – is ‘a prerequisite for
having interests at all’. What he broadly means by ‘interests’ here is the
opportunity for creatures to live their lives to the full. Without sentience,
Singer argues, we can have no interests. A stone has no feelings and can-
not suffer, so a boy kicking it along the street is not harming its interests.

Free download pdf