The History of Mathematics: A Brief Course

(coco) #1
314 10. EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY

10.19. When the equation y^2 = Cx - kx^2 is converted to the standard form

a2 + b^2 '

what are the quantities h, a, and b in terms of C and fc?

10.20. Show from Apollonius' definition of the foci that the product of the distances

from each focus to the ends of the major axis of an ellipse equals the square on half

of the minor axis.

10.21. We have seen that the three- and four-line locus problems have conic sections

as their solutions. State and solve the two-line locus problem. You may use modern

analytic geometry and assume that the two lines are the χ axis and the line y = ax.

The locus is the set of points whose distances to these two lines have a given ratio.

What curve is this?

10.22. Show that the apparent generality of Apollonius' statement of the three-line

locus problem, in which arbitrary angles can be prescribed at which lines are drawn

from the locus to the fixed lines, is illusory. (To do this, show that the ratio of a

line from a point Ñ to line / making a fixed angle è with the line / bears a constant

ratio to the line segment from Ñ perpendicular to I. Hence if the problem is solved

for all ratios in the special case when lines are drawn from the locus perpendicular

to the given lines, then it is solved for all ratios in any case.)

10.23. Show that the line segment from a point Ñ = (x,y) to a line ax + by = c

making angle è with the line has length

\ax + by — cj

Use this expression and three given lines : á*÷ + hy = Ci, i = 1,2,3, to formulate

the three-line locus problem analytically as a quadratic equation in two variables by

setting the square of the distance from (i, y) to line l\ equal to a constant multiple

of the product of the distances to fa and I3. Show that the locus passes through

the intersection of the line li with I2 and ^3, but not through the intersection of I2

with i 3. Also show that its tangent line where it intersects Zj is Z* itself, i = 2,3.

10.24. One reason for doubting Cavalieri's principle is that it breaks down in one

dimension. Consider, for instance, that every section of a right triangle parallel to

one of its legs meets the other leg and the hypotenuse in congruent figures (a single

point in each case). Yet the other leg and the hypotenuse are obviously of different

lengths. Is there a way of redefining "sections" for one-dimensional figures so that

Cavalieri's principle can be retained? If you could do this, would your confidence

in the validity of the principle be restored?

10.25. We know that interest in conic sections arose because of their application

to the problem of two mean proportionals (doubling the cube). Why do you think

interest in them was sustained to the extent that caused Euclid, Aristaeus, and

Apollonius to write treatises developing their properties in such detail?

10.26. Pappus' history of the conies implies that people knew that the ellipse, for

example, could be obtained by cutting a right-angled cone with a plane. Can every

ellipse be obtained by cutting a right-angled cone with a plane? Prove that it can, by

showing that any a and b whatsoever in Eq. 2 can be obtained as the section of the
Free download pdf