The History of Mathematics: A Brief Course

(coco) #1
348 11. POST-EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRY

three-dimensional Euclidean space that was a perfect model for the Lobachevskii-

Bolyai plane, in the sense that its geodesies corresponded to straight lines and

lengths and angles were measured in the ordinary way, remained open until Hubert,

in an article "Uber Flachen von konstanter Gaufischer Kriimmung" ("On surfaces

of constant Gaussian curvature"), published in the Transactions of the American

Mathematical Society in 1901, showed that no such surface exists.

5.6. Foundations of geometry. The problem of the parallel postulate was only

one feature of a general effort on the part of mathematicians to improve on the

rigor of their predecessors. This problem was particularly acute in the calculus, but

the parts of calculus that raised the most doubts were those that were geometric

in nature. Euclid, it began to be realized, had taken for granted not only the

infinitude of the plane, but also its continuity, and had not specified in many cases

what ordering of points was needed on the line for a particular theorem to be true.

If one attempts to prove these theorems without drawing any figures, it becomes

obvious what is being assumed. It seemed obvious, for example, that a line joining

a point inside a circle to a point outside the circle must intersect the circle in

a point, but that fact could not be deduced from Euclid's axioms. A complete

reworking of Euclid was the result, expounded in detail in Hubert's Grundlagen

der Geometrie (Foundations of Geometry), published in 1903. This book went

through many editions and has been translated into English (Bernays, 1971). In

Hubert's exposition the axioms of geometry are divided into axioms of incidence,

order, congruence, parallelism, and continuity, and examples are given to show what

cannot be proved when some of the axioms are omitted.

One thing is clear: No new comprehensive geometries are to be expected by pur-

suing the axiomatic approach of Hubert. In a way, the geometry of Lobachevskii and

Bolyai was a throwback even in its own time. The development of projective and

differential geometry would have provided—indeed, did provide—non-Euclidean

geometry by a natural expansion of the study of surfaces. It was Riemann, not

Lobachevskii and Bolyai, who showed the future of geometry. The real "action" in

geometry since the early nineteenth century has been in differential and projective

geometry. That is not to say that no new theorems can be produced in Euclidean

geometry, only that their scope is very limited. There are certainly many such

theorems. Coolidge, who undertook the herculean task of writing his History of

Geometric Methods in 1940, stated in his preface that the subject was too vast to

be covered in a single treatise and that "the only way to make any progress is by a

rigorous system of exclusion." In his third chapter, on "later elementary geometry,"

he wrote that "the temptation to run away from the difficulty by not considering

elementary geometry after the Greek period at all is almost irresistible." But to

attempt to build an entire theory as Apollonius did, on the synthetic methods and

limited techniques in the Euclidean tool kit, would be futile. Even Lobachevskii and

Bolyai at least used analytic geometry and trigonometry to produce their results.

Modern geometries are much more algebraic, as we shall see in Chapter 12.

6. Questions and problems

11.1. The figure used by Zenodorus at the main step in his proof of the isoperi-

metric inequality had been used earlier by Euclid to show that the apparent size of

objects is not inversely proportional to their distance. Prove this result by referring
Free download pdf